1 Introduction
By the second half of the 17th century, hydrology was at a crucial passage of its evolution, because scientists were about to fully recognize the Sun as the engine of the hydrological cycle.
The debate on what the engine of the hydrological cycle was, whether it was the Sun or the Earth, is ancient and dates back to Aristotle.
He in fact assumed that, whereas little rivers and small springs could be supplied by subsurface reservoirs, the amount of water flowing in big rivers was too great to be stored in any reservoir and, thus, it could not derive entirely from precipitation.
Therefore he concluded that big rivers must be supplied by a continuous evaporation and condensation process, acting within the Earth as a result of an unknown underground source of heat
Pierre Perrault (1611–1680) was one of the first, if not the first, to uphold such an idea. In his opus De l'origine des fontaines (On the origin of springs; Fig. ), Perrault devised methods of measurement, performed experiments and collected many observations both to assess the water balance at the basin scale and to understand the water movement in the upper soil layers . Perrault seemed to be aware that his measurements of the water balance were quite crude and were affected by some inaccuracies (see Sect. ). However, these errors compensated for each other, so that his assessment of the water balance turned out to be quite correct . A few years later, Perrault's fellow countryman refined and improved his method and offered the first rigorous basin-scale measurement in the history of hydrology. In fact, Perrault paved the way for the effective comprehension of the water cycle, although he himself did not understand it correctly. Indeed even if he showed with his experiments that precipitation might provide much more water than necessary to supply springs and rivers, he still decided to subscribe to Aristotle's position.
Figure 1
Front matter of Perrault's opus De l'origine des fontaines
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
Figure 2Front matter of Schott's opus Anatomia physico–hydrostatica fontium ac fluminum
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
Despite these limits, Perrault's contribution to hydrology has been remarkable, as already illustrated in the seminal article by Raymond L. Nace, published in 1974, on the occasion of the Tercentenary of Scientific Hydrology .
The Origine contains a number of significant insights into various hydrological matters, such as the ideas of bank and floodplain storage and return flow (even if he had no name for these processes).
He also proposed several accurate observations on soil, weather and climate, not to speak of his astute reflections on phenomena like evaporation, condensation and infiltration
The aim of this paper is to clarify the new frame of mind, which made hydrology possible as a science. Indeed, hydrology needed two steps in order to become a modern science: they were the concept of scientific experiment and the assessment of the quantitative evaluation of the water cycle. Perrault took both these steps. His work therefore allows an understanding of how the birth of modern hydrological science was strictly linked to the scientific revolution of the 17th century (referred to as the Scientific Revolution hereafter). In fact, Perrault paved the way to scientific hydrology because he had a new, critical attitude towards tradition, also shared with scientist–philosophers like Descartes and Pascal .
For this purpose, we will reconstruct the cultural and intellectual context in which Perrault operated, highlighting the similarities between his position and that of the major scientists and philosophers of the age (Sect. ). Afterwards, we will focus more specifically on Perrault's book, adopting a comparative method of analysis, to show the novelty of his approach to hydrological matters compared to his contemporary Gaspar Schott (Sect. ). Then, we will analyse Perrault's experiments in depth and present today's repetition of them, on the basis of the reports contained in his book, thus stressing the importance of the notion of repeatability (Sect. and ). In the following section we will enhance the didactical aspects of Perrault's experiments, which can be used to illustrate the general aspects of the scientific practice and the specific problems connected with soil hydrology (Sect. ). In the conclusion, we will go into more detail about Perrault's epistemological assumptions, contained in his Letter to Mr. Huygens, by showing interesting correspondences between Perrault's anti-dogmatic and problematizing approach, and some issues arising from the modern paradigm of complexity in hydrology (Sect. and Conclusion).
2 Perrault's cultural and scientific contextPerrault's seminal opus may be framed in the context of the querelle des anciens et des modernes (controversy between the ancients and the moderns), a spirited debate that took place in France during the second half of the 17th century and had profound resonances all over Europe . Although the controversy emerged in a literary milieu, it rapidly spread in the scientific field and became entwined with the debates of the nascent Scientific Revolution. Pierre Perrault was a cultured man of noble origin and he played a role in the controversy, as well as his brothers, who were prominent figures in various fields of politics and culture . For instance Perrault's brother Charles, a renowned poet of the age, was the author of four volumes that focused on the question of whether the primacy in art and knowledge should lie with the ancients or with the moderns .
The epistemological meaning of this dispute was immediately evident for the intellectuals of the age: at stake there was the correct way of achieving the truth. Whereas the supporters of the ancients defended the pre-eminence of the old principle of authority, the moderns put forward the idea that knowledge must be grounded only on reason and experience. The querelle can thus be seen as the way French intellectuals of the âge d'or dealt with the deep cultural transformations of their time. The comparison between modern knowledge and skills and those inherited from antiquity represented for them an effort to become aware of the historical and intellectual break-up they were living in. Like his brother Charles, Pierre Perrault sided with the moderns in his research field and applied the new experimental method to the problems of hydrology for the first time. Therefore, it is not surprising to find in his writings a strong reflection of the spirit of the Scientific Revolution and a thorough awareness of its achievements. He appears fully conscious of the difference between his own approach and that of his predecessors and considers the experiments as the primal source of scientific knowledge:
I know all too well that it is to experiments that we owe the finest knowledge we now have concerning the things of nature which had been unknown to Antiquity; and I base myself only on such principles.
As for the other disciplines, in so far as they borrow their principles from philosophy, I concluded that nothing solid could have been built on such shaky foundations.
A similar centrality of experience can be found also in Pascal's Préface pour un traité du vide (Preface to the treatise on vacuum, written in 1651), which is another relevant reference to understand Perrault's position . Here, the French philosopher and scientist states that whereas authority is essential with regard to literary and historical issues, it is useless in the domain of matters that fall under our senses, such as the investigation of nature. In a few pages Pascal establishes the basis for the separation between humanistic and scientific attitudes, which still persists nowadays, yet with important differences . In fact, Pascal's separation between the so-called “two cultures” is an argument against those academicians who wished to submit science to the dogmatic authority of metaphysics and theology. According to the author, the investigation of nature is characterized by “freedom”, as it is based on experience, whereas “dogmatism” is typical of literary, philosophical and theological studies. This position paved the way to the overcoming of Aristotelianism: as long as experience plays a crucial role, the philosopher's word could not be authoritative in the knowledge of nature. In his Avertissement Perrault shares this posture towards the past authors without falling into arrogance, as he claims that
It is not an extraordinary thing to examine the ideas of any author, it is permitted to the least disciples to ask the most renowned Philosophers, in the very school where they have most credit, the reasons for the propositions that they have advanced.
3 Comparison between Schott's and Perrault's opus
The depth of the paradigmatic novelty fostered by Perrault with his opus may be recognized by comparing the Origine with another opus, the Anatomia physico–hydrostatica fontium ac fluminum (Physical–hydrostatic anatomy of springs and rivers; Fig. ), published only one decade before by the Jesuit Gaspar Schott . The Origine was written in French to be accessible to a broader audience, whereas the Anatomia was written in Latin. In his opus, Schott carefully reviews and discusses the opinions of ancient and modern authors about the origin of springs and rivers (see Table ). Finally he states his own conjecture, according to which (a) the sea is the origin of most of the springs, and (b) the water rises from the sea mostly due to the greater altitude of the sea, with respect to the mountains. A comparison between the form and structure of the two texts reveals further important differences, despite the short lapse of time which separates them.
Table 1
List of previous scholars referred to by and by .
Scholar | ||
---|---|---|
Agricola | p. 110 | p. 48 |
Albertus Magnus | pp. 117–121 | |
Aristotle | pp. 66–76 | pp. 13–21 |
Cabeus Nicolas | pp. 111–114 | |
Cardano | pp. 40–49 | |
Coimbran philosophers | pp. 106–109 | pp. 35–38 (together with Thomas Aquinas) |
Cornelius a Lapide | pp. 114–117 | |
Davity | pp. 89–90 | |
Descartes | pp. 82–84 | pp. 90–97 |
Dobrzenzki de Nigro Ponte | pp. 49–51 | |
Du Hamel | pp. 117–124 | |
Epicurus | pp. 21–22 | |
Froidmond Libert | pp. 109–110 | |
Gassendi | pp. 116–117 | |
Holy Scriptures and Patristics | pp. 88–102 | |
P. (père) Jean François | pp. 142–145 | |
P. (père) Lennart Leys (Leonardus Lessius) | pp. 77–78 | |
Lucretius | pp. 96–99 | |
Maignan | pp. 126–128 | (see Schott) |
Palissy | pp. 145–146 | |
Papin | pp. 97–116 | |
Presocratic philosophers | p. 74 | |
Plato | pp. 49–53, 78 | p. 8 |
Plinius | pp. 32–35 | |
Rohault | pp. 138–142 | |
Scaliger (Julius Caesar Scaliger) | pp. 38–40 | |
Schott | pp. 115, 124–138 | |
Scotus Duns | pp. 121–125 | |
Seneca | pp. 77, 86–88 | pp. 24–32 |
Other scholars reported by Seneca | p. 85 | pp. 27–30 |
Thomas Lydiat | pp. 129–130 | pp. 72–88 |
Vallès Francisco (Vallesius) | pp. 103–106 | pp. 33–34 |
Vitruve | pp. 22–24 | |
von Helmont | pp. 51–72 |
Authors referred to as Opinion Commune by Perrault.
The Anatomia appears to be an opiniones (opinions) book, deeply rooted in the ancient humanistic and dialectical approach and far from the modern scientific method.
It is noteworthy that Schott felt it necessary to focus on histories of ancient springs, drawn by classic literary sources, in which mythological and imaginary witnesses are mixed together with historical and geographical accounts
By contrast, Perrault's opus provides, for each author discussed, a clear separation between exposition and critique and, most importantly, he motivates his objections on the basis of the experimental results which are presented in the “Second Part” of the work.
He does not consider the Holy Scriptures as a pertinent source in the context of his work.
This choice represents another indication of his critical attitude towards the principle of authority.
Furthermore, Perrault discusses a set of authors that he defines as supporters of the Opinion Commune (common opinion)
It is in our opinion no coincidence that Schott did not refer to Palissy's work. Indeed Bernard Palissy was not a scholar, but a ceramic artist. His strong commitment to technical investigation is reflected also in the Discours admirable (The admirable discourses), where he imagines a polemical dialogue between the personifications of Theory and Practice . The triumph of the latter signifies the superiority of the “vulgar methods” over the scholastic and speculative approach of the traditional philosophy of nature. Although Perrault argues against Palissy and the common opinion, he agrees with him that practice could teach more than books about nature. However, Palissy's approach still reflects a Renaissance idea of experience, related to craft work, in which an artist craftsman subjectively learns from his experience and on the basis of his own sensibility. By contrast, the Scientific Revolution broke the tie between art and knowledge of nature, the latter deriving from a series of ordered experiences whose objectivity is guaranteed by the repeatability of measurements. Perrault does not only affirm the superiority of experience over authority, but he also performs an experiment and, most importantly, provides an experimental report whose accuracy fits the standards of modern scientific practice. Differently from Palissy, Perrault felt the necessity of submitting concrete and checkable results in order to support his thesis.
The crucial difference with Schott's opus lies, indeed, in the fact that Perrault supports his theses with the report of an experimental activity. In fact, the reference to experience is not absent in the Anatomia but Schott did not perform any experiment first-hand, and his exposition does not have the characteristics of experimental report. In his book, he mentions some observations recently made by about the capability of water to rise within a soil column:
Fill, with dry sand, a glass pipe opened on both sides, then cover the lower mouth with a cloth so that the sand cannot pour out;
and dip the covered mouth into water only to the depth of a transverse finger:
you will observe that water rises a little and all the sand is wetted, up to the height of three palms above the surface of the water [which is] in a vessel.
After discussing previous authors' opinions
Figure 3
Statement of Perrault's opinion
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
The remaining part of the Origine contains a general discussion of the hydrological cycle, in which Perrault shows some evidence for the fact that about one-sixth of precipitation is sufficient to provide rivers with flowing water
Measurement systems used in 17th-century France .
Measurement unit | pied du roi | Toise de l'Ècritoire | Toise du Châtelet |
---|---|---|---|
(before 1667) | (since 1668) | ||
point | |||
ligne | |||
pouce | |||
pied du roi (pied) | |||
toise |
On p. 154 of the Origine, introduces the experimental activity he performed to clarify the two doubts previously mentioned. We reproduce here his note in the English translation:
Before beginning the discussion of these two difficulties, I wish to describe here an experiment I have made, which may shed a little light on what we have to say.
During the first experiment Perrault took a lead pipe, long and with a diameter of .
He closed it on one side with a cloth and filled it with river sand, sieved with a coarse sieve.
He held the pipe vertically and dipped it into a wide water-filled vessel, leaving it in this position for one day.
After 24 h, as he reported, he found that the water rose within the soil up to .
At this point it is not clear how he performed this observation, as elsewhere (at the end of the description of the first experiment) he reports that in order to appreciate how the soil was wetted, he needed to shake the pipe to let the soil slide out.
Maybe he reports here a measurement that he performed at the end of the experiment, or he extracted the sand, made the measurement and then filled the pipe again to proceed with new measurements.
As a first conclusion he reports that he was surprised at such a rise of the water within the column.
Then he wanted to check whether a spring could spontaneously outcrop above the water surface.
He therefore made a hole about above the water surface, with a diameter between and .
He added a long spout that sloped toward the vessel, without touching the water surface.
In order to restore the medium continuity between the inside and the outside of the pipe, the spout was covered with grey paper, to show any possible wetting, and with a thin layer of sand.
He commented that in the case a spring had onset, then perpetual motion would have been established.
On the contrary he only observed that the sand and the paper were wetted, without producing any drop of water.
It is worth noting that this case was already recognized by in his Fig. XI (see Fig. in this paper).
According to it a spring might start only if the extreme end of the spout (a cloth, in Schott's example) was below the water surface in the vessel.
Afterwards Perrault suspended the pipe over an empty vessel in order to check whether the soil allowed some water to drain, but also in this case no water was collected in half a day's time.
Then he added a certain amount of water twice (the amount of water is not specified).
The day after the first imbibition he collected three-quarters of the added water, and the day after the second one he collected all the added water.
Finally he wanted to evaluate the water content of the soil and shook the pipe in order to let the soil slide out.
He thus recognized that the lower part of the soil was thoroughly wetted as “very wet mortar”
Perrault's description of the soils used during the first and second experiment.
Perrault's description | |
---|---|
First | Dry river sand, passed with coarse sieve |
Second | Sand with gravel |
Third | Crumbled and sieved sandstone |
Fourth | Crumbled granular soil |
Height of capillary rise and characterization of Perrault's soils (first, second, third, fourth) and of the soils used for the repetitions of the first experiment (A, B, C). : porosity; : characteristic diameter for the Polubarinova-Kochina's relationship; : characteristic diameter for Kozeny and Carman's relationship; : Polubarinova-Kochina's capillary rise; : Kozeny and Carman's intrinsic permeability; : Kozeny and Carman's hydraulic conductivity at saturation. Perrault's soils are described in Table .
Height of capillary rise | ||||||||||
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Perrault's | After | Limit | ||||||||
data | one day | rise | ||||||||
(cm cm) | () | () | () | () | () | () | () | (m s) | ||
First | 0.333 | 0.0185 | (0.0185) | 18 | 48.7 | 1.58E | 1.55E | |||
Second | 0.333 | 0.0332 | (0.0332) | 10 | 27.1 | 5.11E | 5.01E | |||
Third | 0.333 | 0.0332 | (0.0332) | 10 | 27.1 | 5.11E | 5.01E | |||
Fourth | 0.333 | 0.0185 | (0.0185) | 18 | 48.7 | 1.58E | 1.55E | |||
A | 0.463 | 0.0268 | 0.0444 | 20.1 | 21.8 | 19.4 | 3.77E | 3.70E | ||
B | 0.478 | 0.0165 | 0.0241 | 26.5 | 28.1 | 29.7 | 1.29E | 1.27E | ||
C | 0.440 | 0.0198 | 0.0340 | 25.45 | 26.65 | 28.2 | 1.74E | 1.71E |
Figure XI from Schott's opus Anatomia physico–hydrostatica fontium ac fluminum
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
Perrault performed a third experiment to check whether the rainfall water could reach a layer of impervious soil or rock, where it could stop and rise to form a spring.
In order to do so, he took the pipe and filled it with dry and sieved loam, compacting it with a rod.
He suspended the pipe over an empty vessel and poured many times the amount of water contained in a glass vial, which was filled up to the spout, and which had the same volume as a medium ball of the jeu de paulme
In the fourth reported experiment, Perrault aimed at testing whether salty water, rising by capillarity within the soil, maintained its salt content or if it left it in the sand. As in fact spring water is commonly fresh, this was considered a key aspect in understanding the circulation of water within the Earth. Perrault's report is not detailed in this case, but he only notes that, after the water rose in the sand column up to , the sand was salty both at the top and at the bottom. He guessed that, if the sand at the top was less salty than that at the bottom, it probably meant that the soil was less wet at the top than at the bottom.
About two pages
First I know that Magnanus' opinion [Maignan's opinion] is not acceptable, and that it is based on a fact which is only half true: upon which I note in passing that what I have said elsewhere is really correct, that most of those who make experiments on discoveries of which they wish to pass as the Authors, will look at them only in the aspect that serves their ends, as did Magnanus who only wanted to prove the absorption of water by the Earth.
After what I have just observed concerning the two difficulties which I have found in the common opinion, I think it must be agreed that the penetration of the Earth by rain water cannot be achieved according to this opinion; and the rains to which it attributes the origin of springs not being enough to produce them, and still less to cause them to flow continually, it is proper to reject this view.
The great detail of Perrault's experimental report left us with two questions: (a) Are Perrault's experiments really qualitatively and quantitatively repeatable in the laboratory? (b) Is it possible, on the basis of Perrault's data, to infer what the hydrological properties of his soils could be? The questions were addressed both in the laboratory and with numerical simulations . Some aspects of the numerical simulations will be mentioned in the next section. Here the main laboratory procedures and results will be summarized. The experimental details and data are fully reported by .
A polycarbonate pipe of in diameter, cut to a length of , mimicked Perrault's lead pipe. A punched metal plate and a cloth of nonwoven fabric were used to hold the soil and to drain the water when the column was held in a vertical position (Fig. ). Three quarry sands, commonly used in building works, were chosen to repeat the experiments. In the following the soils will be referred to as A, B and C, according to the order in which they were used for the repetitions. The grain size distribution curves were determined by dry sieving, since the fine soil component was negligible. The soils were classified as coarse-to-medium sand (A, C) and medium-to-fine sand (B). The soils were poorly graded, with a uniformity coefficient of about for A and B, and about for C ( and are the equivalent diameters which retain and of the soil weight, respectively). The hydraulic conductivity at soil saturation was difficult to estimate by means of the laboratory falling-head permeameter, because expected values were greater then m s. It was therefore estimated by means of Kozeny and Carman's equation (see Eq. in the Appendix). The soil-water retention relationships were measured by means of Richards' pressure plates for pressure values , and by means of a hydrostatic method for . The couples , where is the gravimetric water content, were interpolated by means of Brooks and Corey's retention curve (Eq. ) and van Genuchten's retention curve (Eq. ), both with or without the usual constraints (Eq. ) on and . An example of the obtained soil-water retention relationships is represented in Fig. for the medium-to-fine sand (soil B). Values at were too sparse and were not used for the regressions.
Figure 5
Laboratory setup of the soil column (a) and the soil column during the second part of the first experiment, when the top and the bottom imbibition fronts meet (b).
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
Figure 6Experimental and interpolated soil-water retention relationships of one of the sandy soils used to repeat Perrault's experiments. B: soil identification; : experimental data; B&C: Brooks and Corey's curve; vG: van Genuchten's curve; 6 and 9 are the number of experimental points which were used to interpolate the analytical curves.
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
In Fig. and in Tables and the results of the repetitions of the first experiment are reported. The unitary amount of water poured on the soils was in this case for all the soils, as determined by . All the soils showed a qualitative and (to some extent) a quantitative agreement, both during the spontaneous imbibition from the bottom, and during the forced imbibition from the top. In Table the capillary rises, measured after one day, and the upper limit values of the capillary rises are compared both with data reported by Perrault and with the capillary rise (cm) determined by Polubarinova-Kochina's relationship : 1 In Eq. () is the soil porosity. The good agreement between the measured capillary rise and allows us to infer that Perrault's soils almost reached their asymptotic capillary rise. Thus, accounting for a porosity one-third (because Perrault estimated the amount of water in the soil as one-third of the wetted soil volume) it is possible to estimate the competent characteristic diameter (values are reported in Table ).
Table 5Imbibition and percolation volumes measured during the first experiment. Data are reported as the number of vials, in order to make a comparison with Perrault's data. The unitary volume of a vial was estimated to be equal to for all the soils, according to .
Imbibition | Perrault's data | A | B | C |
---|---|---|---|---|
(vial) | (vial) | (vial) | (vial) | (vial) |
1 | 0.75 | 0.34 | 0.09 | 0.24 |
1 | 1 | 0.92 | 0.76 | 0.73 |
Measures of the position of the water fronts and of the imbibition and percolation volumes collected during the three repetitions of the first experiment. The unitary volume of a vial was estimated to be equal to for all the soils, according to . A, B, C: soil identification; : upward moving water front; : downward moving water front; : percolation volume; dashed line: imbibition volume.
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
Characterizing the hydraulic conductivity at soil saturation is less immediate because the information given by Perrault about the percolation times is incomplete. If we consider that (at least) some of Perrault's soils were sieved, in order to remove the coarse fraction, we hypothesize that the characteristic diameter , determined by Polubarinova-Kochina's equation (Eq. ), is an approximation of the equivalent diameter (Eq. ) needed to determine by Kozeny and Carman's equation (Eq. ). Comparing and as determined for soils A, B and C (Table ) this conjecture may be considered realistic.
Another interesting comparison between Perrault's experiments and their repetition was done with regard to the amount of water that was added and that percolated. The imbibition and percolation volumes are represented in Table . Values are expressed as the number of vials and in this case the volume of a vial was assumed to be equal to . Data are qualitatively in agreement, and although they differ numerically, it emerges that Perrault's data are complete and quantitatively comparable. The same data are presented in Figs. and and in Table for the third experiment. It is worth recalling that in this case the volume of 1 vial was chosen with reference to the capability of the soil to retain water. In fact in his conclusions regarding the experimental activity, Perrault stressed his point of view about the proneness of a soil to allow water to drain. Here he considered that drainage may happen when the soil is wetted with an amount of water which corresponds to one-third of the wetted volume of soil at equilibrium. In the conclusions in fact he states
that in order to wet earth and make it ready for penetration as much water as one third the height and thickness of the earth is necessary.
Imbibition and percolation volumes measured during the third experiment. Data are reported as the number of vials, in order to make a comparison with Perrault's data. The unitary volume of a vial was estimated to be equal to 31.3, 50.5 and 41.0 for soil A, B and C, respectively, according to the procedure described in Sect. .
Time | Imbibition | Perrault's data | A | B | C |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
(d) | (vial) | (vial) | (vial) | (vial) | (vial) |
0 | 4 | 0.33 | 0.09 | 0 | 0.04 |
1 | 2 | 2 | 1.76 | 1.69 | 1.72 |
4 | 2 | 1.75 | 1.36 | 1.72 | 1.61 |
Measures collected during the three repetitions of the third experiment: depth of the imbibition fronts (a) and volumes of imbibition and percolation (b). The unitary volume of a vial was estimated to be equal to 31.3, 50.5 and 41.0 for soil A, B and C, respectively, according to the procedure described in Sect. . A, B, C: soil identification; : downward moving water front; : percolation volume; dashed line: imbibition volume.
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
Figure 9Imbibition and percolation volumes during the three repetitions of the third experiment expressed as the number of vials. The unitary volume of a vial was estimated to be equal to 31.3, 50.5 and 41.0 for soil A, B and C, respectively, according to the procedure described in Sect. . A, B, C: soil identification; : percolation volume; dashed line: imbibition volume.
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
With regard to the repeatability of Perrault's experiments we may therefore conclude that they are almost completely repeatable, in a qualitative sense. If we assume that a quantitative repetition should not be intended to obtain the same results obtained by Perrault, but to define results which may be compared with Perrault's results on a quantitative basis, we may say that Perrault's experiments are also quantitatively repeatable. In fact, the detail with which Perrault describes his experimental activity allows us (a) to clearly identify most of the quantities that he measured, (b) to make realistic conjectures for the quantities about which the Origine is not precise (i.e. the unitary amount of water added with one vial) and (c) to recognize the lack of information (i.e. the time between the beginning of imbibition, the beginning of drainage and the end of drainage). In the next section some conclusions will also be made with regard to the second question posed at the beginning of this section.
6 Didactics of Perrault's experimentsPerrault's opus and experiments can be used in several didactic ways, meeting the objectives of at least the first three elements of the Dublin descriptors, i.e. knowledge and understanding, applying knowledge and understanding, and making judgements . As a general preliminary aspect, comparing the Origine and the different published models of the hydrological cycle induces the students to reflect on the long scientific path, which was taken to move from initial observations and conjectures to the modern description. It also stimulates an exercise of analysis of current understanding (which may be regarded as our modern Opinion Commune) and the exploration of alternative descriptions.
Focusing with more detail on soil hydrology, Perrault's experiments offer a wide range of didactic cases, useful to teach and exemplify many aspects of the subject.
As an application of this idea, the experiment was used as an underlying cross-theme of a recently published didactic book .
In fact the description given by Perrault of the first and second experiment offers the opportunity to teach the hydrostatics of the soil water, above a groundwater table and above a capillary barrier, and to present capillary fringe and soil-water retention curves.
The lack of flow through the soil, as reported in the third experiment, is related to the action of the capillary barrier exerted by the cloth at the bottom of the soil column.
It stresses the importance of locally reaching the soil saturation at the soil bottom, before percolation starts, so as to have the continuity of the generalized piezometric potential ( being the pressure potential and the elevation).
This issue is directly related to Perrault's observation regarding the capability of soil to retain water and the difficulties of infiltrated precipitation to percolate.
The field capacity is here defined as the amount of water stored by the soil in practically hydrostatic conditions
The experiments also illustrate the effect of a great variety of boundary conditions. These include the condition of known pressure potential (bottom boundary of the first experiment), of null flux (top boundary of the first experiment) and of seepage (bottom boundary of the third experiment). The condition of known flux at the top boundary does not clearly emerge from the report, because Perrault unfortunately does not say how long the imbibition lasted during the third experiment. This, together with the other incomplete or omitted data, gives the students an opportunity to recognize the completeness or lack of information. Moreover, trying to interpret and understand ancient observations with modern conceptual frameworks makes it challenging to test and apply their new knowledge.
Finally students may face the second question previously introduced, regarding the capability of inferring the hydrological properties of Perrault's soils, on the basis of the data reported. In the previous section the problem of the conductivity at soil saturation was introduced. Now we will focus on the soil-water retention relationships.
If Perrault's soils are regarded to as soils (i.e. soils with a step-wise soil-water retention relationship), the height of capillary rise also defines the soil-water retention relationship as
2
In Eq. () is the effective soil saturation as introduced by Eq. ().
A delta-shaped soil-water retention relationship may be considered a first approximation of the hydrological characteristics of Perrault's soils, but other soil-water retention curves are compatible with the information provided by Perrault.
As an example which is effective for the soil of the first experiment, the hypothesis is introduced that the height of capillary rise of , observed by Perrault, is between the scale factor and the inflexion point of van Genuchten's soil-water retention relationship
In any case both these hypotheses, according to Perrault's epistemological approach, should now be tested with the soils used for the repetitions of Perrault's experiments. The results are reported in Fig. , in which the observed capillary rises are plotted together with Polubarinova-Kochina and with the estimated values of , and . The hypotheses are not rigorously satisfied, but the capillary rises are comparable with , and , and this indicates that to some extent the hypotheses may lead to a realistic approximation of Perrault's soil constitutive laws. The results might be better, if the experimental soil-water retention curves were measured with more detail near saturation. Yet what is important for teaching purposes at this point is that the comparison between the hypotheses and the experimental evidence induces the students to critically analyse their modus operandi, and to understand what the strong constraints of the epistemological approach based on the experimental practice are.
Figure 10Comparison between the measured height of capillary rise after 1 d, the limit height of capillary rise, the height of capillary rise estimated by means of the Polubarinova-Kochina formula, and the absolute values of the characteristic potentials , and for the three soils used to repeat Perrault's experiments.
[Figure omitted. See PDF]
With regard to the second question posed at the beginning of Sect. , we may therefore conclude that (a) it is not possible to define a set of hydrological properties which completely describes one of Perrault's soils, but (b) it is possible to make a set of reasonable hypotheses, which allow a range of realistic values to be defined for the hydrological properties of the described soils.
7 Perrault and the complexityPerrault's discussion to confute the Opinion Commune
What the earth drinks, this Philosopher [Seneca] says, is little … but I add to this reasoning experiments made daily on this penetration of the earth,
To understand this [the second difficulty with the common opinion] completely, one must picture and discuss in detail, how the penetration of the Earth according to the common opinion can be accomplished.
The water that falls on the Earth begins by wetting the parts of the earth or sand nearest to it; then it wets other, more distant parts, then others, always going downward, and wetting the Earth in all its parts one after the other.
Here Perrault, according with his refusal of the principle of authority, challenges his perspective with Aristotle's famous assertion, according to which the total mass flowing from springs or in rivers during one year would be greater than the entire Earth's mass:
The name of its Author, the number of rivers on the Earth and the length of a year, are things that strike the imagination so strongly that it is hard not to be won over to such a likely idea, and such a hard one to argue about.
But without being amazed, let us try to consider this objection, and without distrusting our strength overmuch, let us try to find a solution for it.
but as these reasons bear only on the destruction of the opposing opinion, some attempt must be made to give other reasons that might support the one that I maintain and show that rain waters are enough to cause the flow of springs and rivers for a whole year.
… I shall try nevertheless by making rough estimates of the volume of rains and of that of the flow of rivers, to give some basis for judgement on the opinion that I uphold, and to arrive at such judgement.
It is necessary above all to reach an agreement on ways of measuring these two kinds of water.
only about one-sixth part of the rain and snow water that falls, is therefore needed to cause this river to flow continually for one year.
What is the value given by Perrault to this conclusion? He seems to be aware that the measurements are imprecise and not complete, but in this context, rather than providing exact results, he aims at showing a research path that will lead to the birth of modern hydrology:
I know very well that this deduction has no certainty: but who could give one that would be certain?
Nevertheless whatever this one may be, I believe it is more satisfactory than a simple negative like Aristotle's and that of those who maintain, without knowing why, that it does not rain enough to supply the flow of rivers.
However that may be, until someone makes more exact observations, by which he proves the contrary of what I have advanced, I shall hold to my view, and be content with the feeble light shed by the observations I have made, being unable to have a stronger one.
Since I have found the material of springs of the best quality possible, I mean fresh water in plenty, passed through and purified by pure and clean sands and that it remains for me only to raise it to the mouths of springs, I no longer have any difficulty, all Philosophy, ancient and modern, is with me, and is in agreement that that can be done easily and naturally.
all have remained in agreement about this rising of water or of aqueous vapors to the top of mountains; and this consensus, although based on different principles, is a fairly good sign of the truth of this fact.
The fact that Perrault explains the hydrological cycle by going back to the ancient tradition enlightens some intricate features of the Scientific Revolution, which did not proceed straightforwardly, but which was characterized by alternative phases of advancement and uncertainty. Nevertheless, with his attitude of moving from the laboratory to the field, his research based on common methods of measurement, his acceptance of quantitative observations until they are not falsified by other researchers, Perrault demonstrates the spirit of the Scientific Revolution. Moreover he seems to anticipate some themes which are characteristic of the modern epistemology of complexity. We should probably admit that, already in the 17th century, some scientists realized that the nascent paradigm of classical physics, that focused on the perfect repeatability of an experiment, was inadequate to deal with some natural phenomena. Therefore, the birth of modern hydrology reflected not only the emergence of the scientific method, but also a supplementary epistemological reflection on the limits of laboratory experiments, thus going beyond the common image of the Scientific Revolution.
Apart from what is reflected in the Origine, is it possible to find evidence of this supplementary epistemological reflection in Perrault's opus?
Perrault's Cartesian appeal to simplicity, practice and common sense appears to clash with epistemological awareness.
However, in the Lettre à Mr. Hu[y]guens au sujet des experiences (Letter to Mr. Huygens about experiments, written in 1672 and published as an appendix of the Origine two years later) Perrault demonstrates that he had deeply reflected on the limits of the scientific method
First, according to Perrault, a scientist must never declare himself satisfied with the results of an experiment before he has reached a full agreement between experience and judgement:
For whatever experiments can be performed, one cannot stop there, if judgement and the senses all together do not agree about them: the senses are often mistaken when they act alone, and the judgement is often deceived also sometimes unless the senses set it right.
It is certain that in Nature, no effect is produced by a single cause, and that on the contrary there is none without several causes, some of which are particular to the things on which the effects are produced, and the others are alien to them and come from the outside, and nevertheless take part in the production of their effects.
It appears that proportion is absolutely necessary in machines to make them yield the effects desired; and it is likewise obvious that general conclusions cannot be drawn from many experiments that are made, and that all that may be learned from them is merely that what they show us, can be done with the machines, the instruments and the materials which we have used; and at the same time to make us fear that in making them with other machines and of other proportions, or with other instruments, other materials and in other circumstances, they might have other results.
… if these experiments have caused us to doubt so many things about which we were, so it seemed, very sure, they should cause us to doubt even more many things which we now believe are very certain and cause us to fear that some day posterity will give us the same treatment, and laugh at our Philosophy just as we laugh at that of Antiquity.
Perrault's thesis about the horror vacui has been proved to be wrong, but the questions he raises are noteworthy from many points of view. Above all, in the letter there are neither direct references to his experiments reported in the Origine nor to the basin hydrology. However, the letter was written in 1672, just after the three years in which he was collecting data about the water balance of the Seine river, and it was probably written during the composition of the book. If we consider these circumstances, it might be realistic to think that the hydrological studies of the Origine and the epistemological remarks of the letter deeply influenced each other.
What can be inferred by Perrault's remarks? As for the first argument, it is a classical topos of the Scientific Revolution, and thus it does not depart from the 17th century's paradigm. On the contrary, Perrault's emphasis on the multiplicity of causes may be connected to his studies to understand the hydrological cycle. It is important to stress that, according to Perrault, the multiplicity of causes does not represent an objection, but rather a stimulus for scientific enquiry. Furthermore, there is no contradiction between the epistemology of the letter and the scientific practice of the Origine. Indeed in the forethought of the Origine, which is dedicated to Huygens, Perrault states that
What I have said in my letter to Mr. Hu[y]guens, which is at the end of this book, is not to criticize the experiments, as has been said by a few who had already seen this letter: but only to say that there is no certainty to be drawn from the general conclusion of certain experiments, and on that basis to attribute to certain things certain effects rather than to others, and to exclude from them all other causes, known or unknown.
More generally, despite his undeniable faith in scientific progress, Perrault is significantly conscious of the risks involved in an acritical and dogmatic acceptance of experimental results. Not only he is aware that scientific results are strictly connected to the opportunities offered by technical progress, but he also admits the possibility of new interpretations of the achieved results. He therefore shows an understanding of science as an indefinitely open and perfectible field of knowledge. Although we can consider him as one of the founders of scientific soil hydrology and one of the progenitors of a modern scientific spirit, Perrault did not consider the experiment as an oracle. On the contrary, he clearly saw the risk of underestimating the complexity of the phenomena and the influence of the instruments on the object of observation. Far from being a naïve empiricist, he rejects the blind faith in experimental results as well as the old appeal to authority. To summarize, the Lettre is not only proof of the individual guile and lucidity of the author, it also demonstrates that the birth of quantitative hydrology implied a deep epistemological reflection on the limits of experiments and laboratory models.
8 Conclusions
Perrault framed his main opus, the Origine, in a novel epistemological approach. This approach embraced the new experimental and Galilean method, rooted in quantitative measurements, integrated with the traditional method, based on qualitative observations and on the discussion of conjectures. In the critical section of his opus he presents, in a few pages, a set of four experiments. With these experiments he intended to test two main difficulties he found in the modern understanding of the hydrological cycle, which at that time was about to be accepted. The difficulties were (a) whether the water may spontaneously rise in the soil and form springs, and (b) whether it may easily percolate through the soil to reach an impervious layer, where a groundwater table will form and the water level will rise to form springs.
The experiments are precisely described and most of the measurements are detailed, so that we are able both to repeat them in the laboratory and to recognize incomplete data and missing information. Perrault's idea was therefore not only to test his conjecture, but also to make his experiments repeatable, and in this sense we may regard them as probably the first modern hydrological experiments. Yet two of his observations misled his interpretation of the hydrological cycle: at first he tried to create a spring above what would have been the groundwater table, then he did not recognize the importance of the capillary barrier in confining the water percolation, and in reducing the consequent recharge of the groundwater. The repetition of the experiments and the discussion about their interpretation provide interesting cases. These are useful in allowing hydrology students to learn about the fundamental aspects of epistemology, and to understand the modern theoretical framework of soil hydrology.
Perrault's misinterpretation of the hydrological cycle also opens up a discussion about some attractive epistemological issues. As a result of his experiments, Perrault goes back to accept the undemonstrated theory, rooted in Aristotelian thought, according to which the hydrological cycle is mainly the effect of an evaporation and condensation process that takes place in the centre of the Earth. This was despite his demonstration for the Seine basin that precipitation greatly exceeded his estimate of river flow. This provides some evidence that the Scientific Revolution was not a straightforward line, but, as a great cultural movement, was articulated in alternative phases of advancement and uncertainty. Then, the problems posed by soil hydrology, even at an early stage, appear irreducible to the classical paradigm of the Scientific Revolution. Even if the experiments designed by Perrault have proven to be repeatable, an in-depth analysis of them shows that the questions posed on the hydrological cycle could not be tested by means of a controlled laboratory model.
Perrault's scientific practice, which was many–sided, confronted him with complex issues, such as the hydrological cycle and the catchment water balance.
This objective complexity seems to be reflected in his letter to Huyguens which, although often disregarded, contains remarkable ideas anticipating a modern epistemology.
Perrault should therefore be considered not only as an amateur scientist, but also as a refined scholar who worked at a turning point within the developing epistemology of the Scientific Revolution, being aware of its uncertainties and conflicts.
In one of his essays, the novelist and literary critic Italo Calvino gave several definitions of what in his opinion is a classic.
Among these, the sixth one is “A classic is a book which has never exhausted all it has to say to its readers”
Appendix A Relationships used to characterize soil hydrological properties
A1 Hydraulic conductivity at soil saturation
The hydraulic conductivity at soil saturation was estimated by means of Kozeny and Carman's relationship:
A1 in which [M L T L] is the water unitary weight, [M L T] is the dynamic water viscosity, and the term A2 is the intrinsic permeability [L]. In Eq. () [L] is a characteristic grain diameter of the soil and [L L] is the soil porosity. Knowing the grain size distribution curve of the soil, the characteristic diameter was estimated by means of the weighed harmonic average of the grain size distribution curve diameters : A3 where the weights [M M] are the fraction of the soil passing through the sieve with diameter . Therefore is the soil fraction retained by the sieve and .
A2 Soil-water retention relationshipsThe effective soil saturation is firstly introduced as A4 in which [L L] is the volumetric soil-water content, [L L] is the residual (volumetric) soil water content, and [L L] is the effective porosity, being [L L] the (volumetric) water content at soil saturation.
Soil-water retention relationships were represented in the forms proposed by and by . Brooks and Corey's relationship is A5 where is the effective soil saturation; [M L T L] is the soil-water pressure, which may also be expressed in potential form (i.e. with the length dimension, L); is the bubbling pressure (with the same dimension as ), i.e. the minimum value of the pressure potential for which the gaseous phase is discontinuous; and is the pore-size distribution index. Generally the greater the value of , the greater the soil-grain uniformity is.
Van Genuchten's relationship is A6 where is again the effective soil saturation, is the soil-water pressure or pressure potential, is a scaling factor (with the same dimension as ), and and are shape coefficients. According to , in order to analytically integrate Mualem's predictive form for the conductivity of the unsaturated soil, the shape coefficients are constrained by the following relationship: A7 If and are not constrained, the soil-water retention curve () has an inflexion point at A8 If Eq. () holds, the relationship (Eq. ) takes the following form: A9
Data availability
Data of the experiments are fully reported in the technical report by available at the Università degli Studi di Brescia, Dipartimento di Ingegneria Civile, Architettura, Territorio, Ambiente e di Matematica, Brescia, Italy.
Author contributions
In the preliminary study, SB mainly contributed to the hydrological aspects whereas MS mainly contributed to the epistemological aspects.
Competing interests
The authors declare that they have no conflict of interests.
Special issue statement
This article is part of the special issue “History of hydrology” (HESS/HGSS inter-journal SI). It is not associated with a conference.
Acknowledgements
The authors gratefully thank Keith Beven, Okke Batelaan and Dani Or for the valuable comments and suggestions provided during the review and discussion process of the article.
Review statement
This paper was edited by Keith Beven and reviewed by Okke Batelaan and Dani Or.
You have requested "on-the-fly" machine translation of selected content from our databases. This functionality is provided solely for your convenience and is in no way intended to replace human translation. Show full disclaimer
Neither ProQuest nor its licensors make any representations or warranties with respect to the translations. The translations are automatically generated "AS IS" and "AS AVAILABLE" and are not retained in our systems. PROQUEST AND ITS LICENSORS SPECIFICALLY DISCLAIM ANY AND ALL EXPRESS OR IMPLIED WARRANTIES, INCLUDING WITHOUT LIMITATION, ANY WARRANTIES FOR AVAILABILITY, ACCURACY, TIMELINESS, COMPLETENESS, NON-INFRINGMENT, MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR A PARTICULAR PURPOSE. Your use of the translations is subject to all use restrictions contained in your Electronic Products License Agreement and by using the translation functionality you agree to forgo any and all claims against ProQuest or its licensors for your use of the translation functionality and any output derived there from. Hide full disclaimer
© 2020. This work is published under https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/ (the “License”). Notwithstanding the ProQuest Terms and Conditions, you may use this content in accordance with the terms of the License.
Abstract
The naturalistic and philosophical studies conducted in the second half of the 17th century were crucial both for the birth of modern hydrological science and modern epistemology. Thanks to quantitative observations and to the new experiment-based scientific approach, the Sun was about to be fully recognized as the engine of the hydrological cycle. In this context of great vitality and rapid cultural changes, Pierre Perrault published his classical opus De l'origine des fontaines (On the origin of springs) in 1674. The opus presents a discussion on the origin of springs and contains the report of a set of experiments of water flow through a soil column, which may be considered the first of modern hydrology.
In assessing the importance of Perrault's opus, we will discuss his epistemological relevance by looking at the novelty of his approach, at the repeatability of the experiments, at the intriguing didactic aspects for the modern teaching of hydrology and at his attitude in facing the complexity of hydrological processes.
Perrault places himself in the context of a novel experimental epistemology. On the basis of our analyses he seems to be aware that the processes involved in the hydrological cycle and in soil hydrology are hardly reproducible by means of a controlled laboratory model. This circumstance put the modern scientific approach to a severe test at its very beginning. It is suggested that some of Perrault's epistemological and methodological reflections are precursors of the modern epistemology of complexity. Thus even if Perrault's conclusions followed an ancient opinion, his work is not only seminal for hydrology, but also helps to enlighten some features of the scientific revolution of the 17th century.
You have requested "on-the-fly" machine translation of selected content from our databases. This functionality is provided solely for your convenience and is in no way intended to replace human translation. Show full disclaimer
Neither ProQuest nor its licensors make any representations or warranties with respect to the translations. The translations are automatically generated "AS IS" and "AS AVAILABLE" and are not retained in our systems. PROQUEST AND ITS LICENSORS SPECIFICALLY DISCLAIM ANY AND ALL EXPRESS OR IMPLIED WARRANTIES, INCLUDING WITHOUT LIMITATION, ANY WARRANTIES FOR AVAILABILITY, ACCURACY, TIMELINESS, COMPLETENESS, NON-INFRINGMENT, MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR A PARTICULAR PURPOSE. Your use of the translations is subject to all use restrictions contained in your Electronic Products License Agreement and by using the translation functionality you agree to forgo any and all claims against ProQuest or its licensors for your use of the translation functionality and any output derived there from. Hide full disclaimer