Correspondence to Dr Nicola Panocchia, nephrology, Fondazione Policlinico Universitario A. Gemelli, IRCCS, ROMA, Italy; [email protected]
Background
Persons affected by any form of disability represent just under a fifth of the world population, and recent surveys report trends of further increase due to ageing and associated chronic health conditions.1
During the current COVID-19 pandemic, people living with disabilities have several disadvantages that increase their vulnerability, as summarised in tables 1 and 2.
Table 1Vulnerability factors to COVID-19 in persons with disabilities
Area of vulnerability | Factor |
Prevention and management of infection with SARS-CoV-2 |
|
Other physical health issues |
|
Mental health |
|
Distressing factors and other main factors with negative impact on the lives of people with disabilities
Area of impact | Factor |
Social relationships and community participation |
|
Communication |
|
Adaptive skills |
|
Physical health |
|
Mental health |
|
Additionally, during a crisis, the most concerning public health issue is the allocation of scarce resources such as ventilators and intensive care unit (ICU) beds. Several countries developed specific guidelines to manage access to medical resources, based on age and comorbidities, often denying such resources to older people and people with severe and complex disabilities. Various organisations working for the rights of people living with disabilities2–5 have accused medical institutions of ableism (discrimination and social prejudice against people living with disabilities) in triage.6
Our paper aims to highlight which ethical principles underlie these protocols for the triage of scarce medical resources and, in particular, the extent to which the application of these principles involves a shift in the medical paradigm from person-centred to community-centred medicine.
We believe that this shift would not be consistent with the UN Convention on the Rights of Persons with Disabilities (CRPD),6 to which any guideline on allocation of health resources must refer.
Ableism, access to health services and the futility of treatments
The CRPD reaffirms that all persons with disabilities must enjoy all human rights, including non-discrimination, equality of opportunity and accessibility in healthcare provision. Article 25 of the convention explicitly states that ‘discriminatory denial of health care or health services … on the basis of disability’ must be prevented.
‘Reasonable accommodation’ is one of the main requirements stipulated by the CRPD. It is defined in Article 2 as the ‘necessary and appropriate modification and adjustments not imposing a disproportionate or undue burden, where needed in a particular case, to ensure to persons with disabilities the enjoyment or exercise on an equal basis with others of all human rights and fundamental freedoms’.7 Failure to apply reasonable accommodation implies that it is impossible for people with disabilities to benefit from their rights. However, ableism is a well-known problem in healthcare accessibility.
Ableism refers to the assumption that each individual must meet the arbitrary standards set by the dominant group within society and consequently that persons with disabilities are inferior to able-bodied people or at least have to be postponed in the provision of limited resources or services.8 Ableism still represents an underestimated concept by many healthcare workers and policy makers in evaluating the equity of service provision to patients with disabilities and continues to limit healthcare accessibility. For example, the data in the literature have demonstrated both premature and avoidable mortality of people with autism and learning disabilities.9 In Italy, the ‘Charter of Rights for People Living with Disabilities in Hospital’ indicates the presence of ‘health barriers’10: architectural, organisational and cultural barriers that prevent or limit access to health services of people living with disabilities, hindering their right to health.11
The main principle of ethical and legal justification of the medical act is that its expected benefits should be superior, or at least equal, to the foreseen risks. Physicians must assess the proportionality of treatment and avoid therapeutic and diagnostic obstinacy or the futility of treatment.
Especially when applied to people with severe disabilities, the proportionality and futility of medical treatment are highly debated concepts.
The US National Council of Disability highlights that decisions on the futility of care are affected by the prejudice linked to the quality of life of people living with disabilities, which is considered very poor. However, quality of life must not be evaluated on a functional basis but on a person’s satisfaction with their life.12
Deceased-donor organ donation is the ultimate example of the allocation of poor resources. Even in this context, people with intellectual disabilities are discriminated against, as pointed out by the US National Council of Disability report.13
The decision to exclude or include people with disabilities on the waiting list for transplantation must be based only on clinical data. In patients with learning or cognitive disabilities, health-related quality of life or IQ should not be a parameter to judge eligibility for transplantation.14 15
COVID-19: the scarcity of medical resources and the shift of the medical paradigm
The COVID-19 pandemic led to a shift in the medical paradigm from person-centred medicine to community-centred medicine. This shift gives ‘priority to community health above that of the individual patient in allocating scarce resources’.16 Accordingly, during this epidemic, the patient–physician relationship has also undergone a sudden and profound change and has moved away from the shared decision-making model.17
Medicine should be developed and affirmed by combining strategies and clinical options with the person’s needs and values (person-centred medicine).18 In patient-centred medicine, the care should be ‘respectful of and responsive to individual patient preferences, needs, and values’ and should ensure ‘that patient values guide all clinical decisions’.19 Care should include dignity, compassion and respect, always considering clinical, social, emotional and practical needs.20 21
For people with severe cognitive disabilities, in which decision-making abilities are partially or completely absent, supported decision making has been developed. This is an individualised decision-making process that aims to make people living with disabilities the protagonists of their choices.22
During a public health crisis, the community’s health takes precedence over the individual’s health. According to Berlinger,23 a tension between equality and equity is created from an ethical point of view: ‘expressed through the fair allocation of limited resources and a focus on public safety, and the patient-centered orientation of clinical ethics, expressed through respect for the rights and preferences of individual patients’.
During this pandemic, these models of relationships seem to have been put aside for a return to paternalism. Often under the guise of public health concerns and limited resources available, the physician has abandoned the shared decision-making model. Instead, the crisis standard of care (CSC) is embraced, which is an optimal level of care that could be delivered during a catastrophic event; however, it requires substantial changes in the usual healthcare operations. The principles proposed by the CSC are fairness, duty of care, duty to steward resources, transparency, consistency, proportionality and accountability.24 The CSC describes a framework that should be applied to prioritise the treatment of patients with the aim of maximising benefits. In clinical practice, during triage, it is only physicians who decide through criteria that may be subject to criticism. In several US states, the CSC has been challenged by advocates for people with disabilities because they encapsulate discriminatory guidelines. In addition, it is difficult in clinical practice to merge the triage process with a shared decision-making model. For these reasons, a triage committee should be established.
However, the fact that such a committee could profoundly influence the physician–patient relationship remains a concern, not to mention the ‘medical paternalism’ it might cause. Therefore, it would be appropriate for this committee to have as its members people living with disabilities or their advocates, so that the principle of ‘nothing about us without us’ can be ensured.
The main ethical theories are now faced with this shift of perspective. In particular, principlism from a perspective of community-centred medicine had to shape the principle of autonomy into that of solidarity; this is in contrast to utilitarianism, one of the most commonly employed ethical approaches in Anglo-Saxon cultures.
Savulescu et al 25 argued in favour of the utilitarian approach in the current pandemic. The fundamental principle to pursue is well-being, and freedom and rights are important only insofar as they ensure well-being. The aim is to achieve greater overall well-being, understood in terms of years of life and quality of life, not to save more lives.26
From this approach, Emanuel et al 27 identified four fundamental values that can be interpreted in more than one way, and sometimes, they can even be:
‘Maximise the benefits from limited resources’. This can be interpreted as saving as many patients as possible or maximally increasing life expectancy by prioritising patients who are more likely to survive.
‘Treat every patient equally’. Equality can be applied by either casually selecting patients or distributing resources on a ‘first come, first served’ basis.
‘Promote and reward the value of work’. This provides people who can save lives or people that have saved lives priority access to limited medical resources.
‘Give priority to those who are in critical conditions’. This encourages the prioritisation of critically ill patients. These patients could either be the most clinically ill or the youngest whose life expectancy could drastically decrease if not properly treated.
Prioritarianism is another interesting perspective, which combines the criterion of general well-being by giving greater weight to worse-off individuals. Nielsen28 argued that, also in pandemic crisis, severity of illness and age should not over-ride the social disadvantage, and this should remain a primary concern. Health policies should be put in place to relieve the effects of inequality amplified by the pandemic.
However, all of these recommendations do not specifically address the issues related to disability.
COVID-19: the scarcity of medical resources and people living with disabilities
Several institutions have proposed guidelines and recommendations about the rightful allocation and management of scarce resources. The Code of Medical Ethics of the American Medical Association (AMA) defines specific criteria to assess patients’ priority access to scarce medical resources as follows:
Medical need (urgency of need).
Likelihood of benefits.
Change in the quality of life.
Patients whose access to treatment might be fundamental to avoid premature death or extremely poor outcomes .
The use of an objective, flexible and transparent mechanism to determine the patients that will receive access to medical resources or treatment when there are no substantial differences among patients.
The AMA Code also states that ‘it is not appropriate to base allocation policies on social worth, perceived obstacles to treatment, patient contribution to illness, past use of resources, or other non-medical characteristics’.
The British Medical Association ethical guidelines present critical issues regarding the applicability of reasonable adjustment.29 To evaluate the benefits of intensive treatments, on its website, the National Institute for Health and Care Excellence has proposed the use of the clinical frailty scale. However, this scale cannot be applied to people with long-term disabilities.
The Italian Society of Anesthesia Analgesia and Resuscitation proposed general criteria to maximise the benefits for as many people as possible and consume the least resources possible to expand the number of beneficiaries. Age, probability of survival, life expectancy, the presence of comorbidities and functional status30 are some of these exclusion criteria. The document highlights that denying access to intensive care by basing the decision solely on the criteria of distributive justice finds justification in the extraordinary nature of the situation.
The French Society of Anesthesia & Intensive Care Medicine states that in crises, it is not justifiable to renounce the principles of autonomy, benevolence, non-maleficence, solidarity and equity as distributive justice. Maximising the benefit and considering the indirect benefit are other principles that should be respected. The resources must be allocated without discrimination of age, religion, sex, presence of a disability, or social and economic position. However, age and presence of a disability should be considered when assessing the prognosis.31
It was also proposed to assign a score to all patients with an indication of requiring ICU hospitalisation, without exclusions a priori, based on: (1) the probability of surviving the hospitalisation by objectively assessing the severity of the acute disease; (2) the probability of long-term survival determined by the presence of comorbidities that decrease life expectancy; and (3) and priority for those who carry out works of public utility.32
Allocation criteria for people living with disabilities: a proposal
Even when not explicitly stated, most of the previously cited criteria do not seem to root for the allocation of scarce resources to people living with disabilities. Kittay33 argued how maximising benefits creates overt discrimination towards people living with disabilities. According to Kittay, ‘the benefits are unlikely to benefit disabled people, and surely not people with intellectual disabilities…. Benefits attach to people. So, who is benefited, and who decides what a benefit is or when it is maximized?’ Prejudices and public perception of people with disabilities and their quality of life can be easily and unfortunately included in the protocols for the rationing of health resources.
Some organisations have claimed the right of people living with disabilities to undergo medical treatment, regardless of the benefit that the treatment will bring. This claim goes against the principles of medical ethics and risks turning into unnecessary suffering and pain for the patient who could be forced to undergo futile treatments.34 35
None of the guidelines and recommendations examined recommend the use of Quality Adjusted Life Years (QALYs) to prioritise resource allocation. QALY is a controversial methodology for cost effectiveness analysis. It was accused of discriminating against people with disabilities and of considering their life of lesser worth.36–39 Two documents, one of National Council of disability, other of Partnership to Improve Patient Care organisation, argued against using the QALY40 41
‘Primum non-nocere’ (non-maleficence) is one of the foundational ethical principles in medicine, and only therapies that are of real benefit to the patient should be proposed. In this context of resource scarcity, the challenge is to blend patient-centred medicine and community-centred medicine. Only in this way can the most vulnerable people be protected, including people living with disabilities. Even for the allocation of scarce resources in triage, people living with disabilities should be treated based on the equality of opportunities and non-discrimination, in accordance with the United Nations Charter of the Rights of Persons with Disabilities. Reasonable accommodation must also be applied in triage and care.
To this purpose, the National Health Service in the UK has developed clinical guidelines to support the management of patients with a learning disability and autism during the COVID-19 pandemic.42
On behalf of The Italian scientific committee of the Charter of Rights of People Living with Disabilities in Hospital and the Italian Disabled Advanced Medical Assistance Centres,43 the authors suggest the following criteria for allocating scarce resources to people living with disabilities:
The principles of non-discrimination, equality, equality of opportunity, reasonable accommodation and the right to health under the CRPD must always be considered and applied.
For people living with disabilities, the risk of death from respiratory failure is greater compared with the general population.4 44–46
It is necessary to consider the impact of intensive care treatments on near-term survivability and overall prognosis for that specific patient with a disability.47
Long-term survival is not an acceptable parameter to determine whether to withhold or withdraw life support treatments.48
Intellectual disability alone should not be accepted as an exclusion criterion.
The expected quality of life of people living with disabilities and QALY should not be relied on.
Usefulness to society cannot be accepted as the only criterion.
People living with disabilities, even those with intellectual disabilities, should be involved in the decision-making processes according to their understanding and decision-making skills; this satisfies the legitimate request ‘Nothing about us without us’.
Allow visits to caregivers of hospitalised people living with disabilities. Many hospitals have very restrictive policies. The caregiver is an indispensable tool to understand the needs (eg, pain) and wishes of the patient better in the context of shared decision making or supported decision making.
If there are the conditions to undertake or suspend a specific treatment, palliative care must be guaranteed.
Advanced care planning is a useful tool to identify the best therapeutic strategy and decision for every patient.
These associations are promoting actions for these criteria’s dissemination and acceptance both from a cultural and regulatory point of view.
Conclusions
Persons with disabilities do not have special rights but do need special tools that guarantee the rights they share with every other people. The CRPD states these universal rights and prescribes various tools for assuring them: principles of non-discrimination, equality, equality of opportunity, the right to health and reasonable accommodation. However, we found that the ethics underlying most recommendations and guidelines for allocating scarce health resources may be based on principles that discriminate against persons with disabilities.
While it is not easy, it is necessary to try to save the specificity of medical care for each patient and the value of each human life even in the current pandemic. We also believe that during a crisis and when dealing with scarcity of resources, the proportionality of treatment should guide decision making.49 50 The ‘principle of therapeutic proportionality’ affirms the moral obligation to provide patients with treatments that preserve a relationship of due proportion between the means employed and the end sought. The benefits and risks associated with the treatment, the expected outcomes, the burdens in terms of quality of life and the physical and moral strength of the individual patient must be considered for this assessment. The authors believe that for an individual patient, in a certain context, the benefits should outweigh the burdens in terms of risks and complications of treatment, quality of life, and physical and moral strength.
The shift from person-centred to community-centred medicine offers both risks and opportunities: the interests of the individual are sacrificed for the safety and health of the community, and this may especially affect the most vulnerable people. However, privileging the health of an entire community can also be a tool to protect the most vulnerable ones included within the community, but this can only happen if the community treats these people as full members. Recommendations and guidelines for the allocation of scarce health resources need to consider the rights of the most vulnerable, including people with disabilities; in particular, they must always apply the principle of reasonable accommodation.
Data availability statement
There are no data in this work.
Contributors NP: conception and design of paper; drafting the article or revising it; providing intellectual content of critical importance to the work described; and final approval of the version to be published. VD: conception and design of study; drafting the article or revising it; and final approval of the version to be published. SC, ELP, MB, MLS and FG: drafting the article or revising it; providing intellectual content of critical importance to the work described; and final approval of the version to be published.
Funding The authors have not declared a specific grant for this research from any funding agency in the public, commercial or not-for-profit sectors.
Competing interests None declared.
Provenance and peer review Not commissioned; externally peer reviewed.
1 World Health Organization. World report on disability, 2011. Available: http://www.who.int/disabilities/world_report/2011/report.pdf [Accessed on 28 February 2021 ].
2 Mello MM, Persad G, White DB. “Respecting disability rights—Toward improved crisis standards of care,” New England Journal of Medicine 383 (2020): e26. 10.1056/NEJMp2011997; A. Ne’eman, “Do New York state’s ventilator allocation guidelines place chronic ventilator users at risk? Clarification needed,” 2020; J. J. Fins, “Disabusing the disability critique of the New York State Task Force report on ventilator allocation,”, 2020. Available: https://www.thehastingscenter.org/disabusing-the-disability-critique-of-the-new-york-state-task-force-report-on-ventilator-allocation/
3 Disability Rights Washington. “Complaint Against WA DOH, NHRN, and UWMC,” March 23, 2020, Consortium for Citizens with Disabilities, “Letter to U.S. Department of Health and Human Services,”, 2020. Available: http://www.c-c-d.org/fichiers/Letter-re-COVID-19-and-Disability-Discrimination-final.pdf
4 Fins JJ. Disabusing the disability critique of the new York state Task force report on ventilator allocation, 2020. Available: https://www.thehastingscenter.org/disabusing-the-disability-critique-of-the-new-york-state-task-force-report-on-ventilator-allocation/
5 Ne’eman A. Do New York state’s ventilator allocation guidelines place chronic ventilator users at risk? Clarification needed, 2020a. Available: https://www.thehastingscenter.org/do-new-york-states-ventilator-allocation-guidelines-place-chronic-ventilator-users-at-risk-clarification-needed/
6 Savin S, Guidry-Grimes L. “Confronting disability discrimination during the pandemic,”, 2020. Available: https://www.thehastingscenter.org/confronting-disability-discrimination-during-the-pandemic/
7 United Nations,. “Convention on the rights of persons with disabilities,”. Available: https://www.un.org/development/desa/disabilities/convention-on-the-rights-of-persons-with-disabilities.html
8 Wolbring G. The politics of Ableism. Development 2008b; 51 (2): 252–8. doi:10.1057/dev.2008.17
9 Heslop P, Blair PS, Fleming P, et al. The Confidential inquiry into premature deaths of people with intellectual disabilities in the UK: a population-based study. The Lancet 2014; 383 (9920): 889–95. doi:10.1016/S0140-6736(13)62026-7
10 Spes contra spem. “The charter of the rights of persons with disabilities in hospital,”, 2018. Available: https://spescontraspem.it/wp-content/uploads/2018/07/Charter-of-the-Rights-of-Persons-with-Disabilities.pdf;
11 Panocchia N, Marino M, Sabetta T, et al. Hospital accessibility and clinical pathways for people with disabilities: an Italian survey. Eur J Public Health 2015; 25 (suppl_3): 190–1. doi:10.1093/eurpub/ckv172.048
12 National Council of Disability. “Medical futility and disability bias,”, 2019. Available: https://ncd.gov/sites/default/files/NCD_Medical_Futility_Report_508.pdf
13 National Council of Disability. “Organ transplant discrimination against people living with disabilities,”, 2019. Available: https://ncd.gov/sites/default/files/NCD_Organ_Transplant_508.pdf
14 Bertelli M, Francescutti C, Brown I. Reframing QOL assessment in persons with neurodevelopmental disorders. Annali dell’Istituto Superiore Di Sanit 2020; 56 (2): 180–92.
15 Panocchia N, Bossola M, Vivanti G. Transplantation and mental retardation: what is the meaning of a discrimination? American Journal of Transplantation 2010; 10 (4): 727–30. doi:10.1111/j.1600-6143.2010.03052.x
16 Hastings Center,. “Ethical framework for health care institutions responding to novel coronavirus SARS-CoV-2 (COVID-19),”, 2020. Available: https://www.thehastingscenter.org/ethicalframeworkcovid19/
17 Charles C, Gafni A, Whelan T. Shared decision-making in the medical encounter: what does it mean? (or it takes at least two to tango). Soc Sci Med 1997; 44 (5): 681–92. doi:10.1016/S0277-9536(96)00221-3
18 Tinetti ME, Fried T. “The end of the disease era,” American Journal of Medicine 116, no. 3 (2004): 179–85; A. Spagnolo, “Medicina personalizzata e medicina centrata sulla persona [Personalized medicine and person-centered medicine],”. Medicina e Morale 2017; 66 (no. 4): 433–7.
19 National Research Council. Crossing the quality chasm: a new health system for the 21st century. Washington, DC: National Academies Press, 2001.
20 Morton RL, Sellars M. From patient-centered to Person-Centered care for kidney diseases. Clinical Journal of the American Society of Nephrology 2019; 14 (4): 623–5. doi:10.2215/CJN.10380818
21 Spagnolo A. Medicina personalizzata e medicina centrata sulla persona [Personalized medicine and person-centered medicine]. Medicina e Morale 2017; 66 (no. 4): 433–7.
22 Jameson JM, Riesen T, Polychronis S, et al. Guardianship and the potential of supported decision making with individuals with disabilities. Research and Practice for Persons with Severe Disabilities 2015; 40 (1): 36–51. doi:10.1177/1540796915586189
23 Berlinger NM. “Ethical framework for health care institutions responding to novel coronavirus SARS-CoV-2 (COVID-19). Guidelines for institutional ethics services responding to COVID-19 Managing Uncertainty, Safeguarding Communities, Guiding Practice,”, 2020. Available: https://www.thehastingscenter.org/wp-content/uploads/HastingsCenterCovidFramework2020.pdf
24, et al Hick. “Duty to plan.”. National Academy of Medicine 2020.
25 Savulescu J, Persson I, Wilkinson D. Utilitarianism and the pandemic. Bioethics 2020; 34 (6): 620–32. doi:10.1111/bioe.12771
26 Savulescu, Persson, and Wilkinson. “Utilitarianism and the pandemic”, 2020.
27 Emanuel EJ, Persad G, Upshur R, et al. Fair allocation of scarce medical resources in the time of Covid-19. New England Journal of Medicine 2020; 382 (21): 2049–55. doi:10.1056/NEJMsb2005114
28 Nielsen L. Pandemic prioritarianism. J Med Ethics 2021: doi:10.1136/medethics-2020-106910. [Epub ahead of print: 4 Feb 2021]. doi:10.1136/medethics-2020-106910 33542106
29 British Medical Association,. COVID-19–ethical issues. A guidance note. London: BMA, 2020.
30 Vergano M, Bertolini G, Giannini A. “Clinical ethics recommendations for the allocation of intensive care treatments in exceptional, resource-limited circumstances. Italian Society of Anesthesia, Analgesia, Resuscitation, and Intensive Care (SIAARTI),”, 2020. Available: http://www.siaarti.it/SiteAssets/News/COVID19%20-%20documenti%20SIAARTI/SIAARTI%20-%20COVID-19%20-%20Clinical%20Ethics%20Reccomendations.pdf
31 Société Française d’Anesthésie et de Réanimation [French Society of Anesthesia & Intensive Care Medecine], “Anesthsia and Priorisation des traitements de réanimation pour les patients en état critique en situation d’épidémie de COVID-19 avec capacités limitées [Prioritization of resuscitation treatments for critically ill patients in a COVID-19 epidemic situation with limited resuscitation reception capacities]” 2020 https://sfar.org/download/priorisation-des-traitements-de-reanimation-pour-les-patients-en-etat-critique-en-situation-depidemie-de-covid-19-avec-capacites-limitees/?wpdmdl=25837&refresh=5e9c56e79595d1587304167
32 White DB, Lo B. A framework for rationing ventilators and critical care beds during the COVID-19 pandemic. JAMA 2020; 323 (18): 1773–4. doi:10.1001/jama.2020.5046
33 Kittay E. “People with disabilities are at a disadvantage when scarce medical resources are being allocated,”, 2020. Available: https://www.statnews.com/2020/04/29/people-disabilities-disadvantage-covid-19-scarce-medical-resources/
34 Ne’eman A. When it comes to rationing, disability rights law prohibits more than prejudice, 2020b. Available: https://www.thehastingscenter.org/when-it-comes-to-rationing-disability-rights-law-prohibits-more-than-prejudice/
35 Persad G, Wasserman D. Diversity and solidarity in response to COVID-19, 2020. Available: https://www.thehastingscenter.org/diversity-and-solidarity-in-response-to-covid-19/
36 Pearson SD. Why the coming debate over the QALY and disability will be different. J Law Med Ethics 2019; 47 (2): 304–7. doi:10.1177/1073110519857286
37 Sinclair S. How to avoid unfair discrimination against disabled patients in healthcare resource allocation. J Med Ethics 2012; 38 (3): 158–62. doi:10.1136/medethics-2011-100093
38 Whitehurst DGT, Engel L. Disability discrimination and misdirected criticism of the quality-adjusted life year framework. J Med Ethics 2018; 44 (11): 793–5. doi:10.1136/medethics-2016-104066
39 Persad G. Considering quality of life while repudiating disability injustice: a pathways approach to setting priorities. J Law Med Ethics 2019; 47 (2): 294–303. doi:10.1177/1073110519857285
40 National Council of disability quality-adjusted life years and the Devaluation of life with disability, November 6, 2019. Available: https://ncd.gov/sites/default/files/NCD_Quality_Adjusted_Life_Report_508.pdf
41 Partnership to Improve Patient Care (PIPC). PiPC white paper measuring value in medicine: uses and misuses of the QALY. Available: http://www.pipcpatients.org/uploads/1/2/9/0/12902828/pipc_white_paper_-_measuring_value_in_medicine_-_uses_and_misuses_of_the_qaly.pdf
42 National Health Service,. “Clinical guide for front-line staff to support the management of patients with a learning disability, autism, or both during the coronavirus pandemic–relevant to all clinical specialties,”, 2020. Available: https://www.england.nhs.uk/coronavirus/wp-content/uploads/sites/52/2020/03/C0031_Specialty-guide_LD-and-coronavirus-v1_-24-March.pdf?utm_source=hootsuite&utm_medium=facebook&utm_term=special+needs+jungle&utm_content=SocialOroMedia
43 Ghelma F. The right to health of the person with autistic spectrum disease: the disabled advanced medical assistance (Dama) pathway response. Proceedings of 12th Autism-Europe International Congress, 2019.
44 Oppewal A. “Causes of mortality in older people with intellectual disability: Results from the HA-ID Study,” American Journal on Intellectual and Developmental Disabilities 123, no. 1 (2018): 61–71; J. Trollor et al., “Cause of death and potentially avoidable deaths in Australian adults with intellectual disability using retrospective linked data,” BMJ Open 7, no. 2 (2017): e013489; T. Hirvikoski et al., “Premature mortality in autism spectrum disorder,” British Journal of Psychiatry 208, no. 3 (2016): 232–38; G. Glover and M. Ayub, “How people with learning disabilities die,”, 2016. Available: https://webarchive.nationalarchives.gov.uk/20160704171220/https://www.improvinghealthandlives.org.uk/publications/928/text/css
45 Hirvikoski T, Mittendorfer-Rutz E, Boman M, et al. Premature mortality in autism spectrum disorder. British Journal of Psychiatry 2016; 208 (3): 232–8. doi:10.1192/bjp.bp.114.160192
46 Trollor J, Srasuebkul P, Xu H, et al. Cause of death and potentially avoidable deaths in Australian adults with intellectual disability using retrospective linked data. BMJ Open 2017; 7 (2): e013489. doi:10.1136/bmjopen-2016-013489
47 National Health Service. Clinical guide for front line staff to support the management of patients with a learning disability, autism or both during the coronavirus pandemic–relevant to all clinical Specialities, March 2020. https://www.nice.org.uk/Media/Default/About/COVID-19/Specialty-guides/learning-disability-autism-during-pandemic.pdf
48 Solomon MZ, Wynia MK, Gostin LO. Covid-19 crisis triage — optimizing health outcomes and disability rights. New England Journal of Medicine 2020; 383 (5): e27. doi:10.1056/NEJMp2008300
49 Picozzi M, Pegoraro R. Taking care of the vulnerable: the criterion of proportionality. The American Journal of Bioethics 2017; 17 (8): 44–5. doi:10.1080/15265161.2017.1340997
50 Petrini C, Gainotti S. A personalist approach to public-health ethics. Bull World Health Organ 2008; 86 (8): 624–9. doi:10.2471/BLT.08.051193
You have requested "on-the-fly" machine translation of selected content from our databases. This functionality is provided solely for your convenience and is in no way intended to replace human translation. Show full disclaimer
Neither ProQuest nor its licensors make any representations or warranties with respect to the translations. The translations are automatically generated "AS IS" and "AS AVAILABLE" and are not retained in our systems. PROQUEST AND ITS LICENSORS SPECIFICALLY DISCLAIM ANY AND ALL EXPRESS OR IMPLIED WARRANTIES, INCLUDING WITHOUT LIMITATION, ANY WARRANTIES FOR AVAILABILITY, ACCURACY, TIMELINESS, COMPLETENESS, NON-INFRINGMENT, MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR A PARTICULAR PURPOSE. Your use of the translations is subject to all use restrictions contained in your Electronic Products License Agreement and by using the translation functionality you agree to forgo any and all claims against ProQuest or its licensors for your use of the translation functionality and any output derived there from. Hide full disclaimer
This article is made freely available for use in accordance with BMJ’s website terms and conditions for the duration of the covid-19 pandemic or until otherwise determined by BMJ. You may use, download and print the article for any lawful, non-commercial purpose (including text and data mining) provided that all copyright notices and trade marks are retained. https://bmj.com/coronavirus/usage
Abstract
This research aims to examine access to medical treatment during the COVID-19 pandemic for people living with disabilities. During the COVID-19 pandemic, the practical and ethical problems of allocating limited medical resources such as intensive care unit beds and ventilators became critical. Although different countries have proposed different guidelines to manage this emergency, these proposed criteria do not sufficiently consider people living with disabilities. People living with disabilities are therefore at a higher risk of exclusion from medical treatments as physicians tend to assume they have poor quality of life, whereas access to medical treatment should be based on several parameters, including clinical data and prognosis. However, the COVID-19 pandemic shifts the medical paradigm from person-centred medicine to community-centred medicine, challenging the main ethical theories. We reviewed the main guidelines and recommendations for resources allocation and examined their position toward persons with disabilities. Based on our findings, we propose criteria for not discriminating against people with disabilities in allocating resources. The shift from person-centred to community-centred medicine offers opportunities but also risks sacrificing the most vulnerable people. The principle of reasonable accommodation must always be considered to guarantee the rights of persons with disabilities.
You have requested "on-the-fly" machine translation of selected content from our databases. This functionality is provided solely for your convenience and is in no way intended to replace human translation. Show full disclaimer
Neither ProQuest nor its licensors make any representations or warranties with respect to the translations. The translations are automatically generated "AS IS" and "AS AVAILABLE" and are not retained in our systems. PROQUEST AND ITS LICENSORS SPECIFICALLY DISCLAIM ANY AND ALL EXPRESS OR IMPLIED WARRANTIES, INCLUDING WITHOUT LIMITATION, ANY WARRANTIES FOR AVAILABILITY, ACCURACY, TIMELINESS, COMPLETENESS, NON-INFRINGMENT, MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR A PARTICULAR PURPOSE. Your use of the translations is subject to all use restrictions contained in your Electronic Products License Agreement and by using the translation functionality you agree to forgo any and all claims against ProQuest or its licensors for your use of the translation functionality and any output derived there from. Hide full disclaimer
Details

1 Department of Nephrology, Fondazione Policlinico Universitario A. Gemelli, IRCCS, Roma, Italy; Charter of Rights for People with Disabilities in Hospital, Roma, Italy
2 Department of Nephrology, Fondazione Policlinico Universitario A. Gemelli, IRCCS, Roma, Italy; Facoltà di Medicina e Chirurgia, Università Cattolica del Sacro Cuore, Roma, Italy
3 Charter of Rights for People with Disabilities in Hospital, Roma, Italy; Disabilities Department, Fondazione Istituto Ospedaliero di Sospiro, Sospiro, Italy
4 Association for the Study of Medical Assistance to People with a Disability (ASMeD), Milano, Italy
5 Association for the Study of Medical Assistance to People with a Disability (ASMeD), Milano, Italy; CREA (Research and Clinical Centre), San Sebastiano Foundation, Misericordia di Firenze, Florence, Italy
6 Research Coordination and Support Service, Istituto Superiore di Sanità, Roma, Italy
7 Association for the Study of Medical Assistance to People with a Disability (ASMeD), Milano, Italy; Department of Disabled Advanced Medical Assistance (DAMA), ASST Santi Paolo e Carlo, Milano, Italy, Milano, Italy