Eur. Phys. J. C (2014) 74:2694DOI 10.1140/epjc/s10052-013-2694-1
Letter
Energy quantisation and time parameterisation
Alon E. Faraggi1, Marco Matone2,a
1 Department of Mathematical Sciences, University of Liverpool, Liverpool L69 7ZL, UK
2 Dipartimento di Fisica e Astronomia G. Galilei and Istituto Nazionale di Fisica Nucleare, Universit di Padova, Via Marzolo 8, Padova 35131, Italy
Received: 11 November 2013 / Accepted: 9 December 2013 / Published online: 23 January 2014 The Author(s) 2014. This article is published with open access at Springerlink.com
Abstract We show that if space is compact, then trajectories cannot be dened in the framework of the quantum HamiltonJacobi (HJ) equation. The starting point is the simple observation that when the energy is quantised it is not possible to make variations with respect to the energy, and the time parameterisation t t0 = ES0, implied by
Jacobis theorem, which leads to the group velocity, is ill dened. It should be stressed that this follows directly from the quantum HJ equation without any axiomatic assumption concerning the standard formulation of quantum mechanics. This provides a stringent connection between the quantum HJ equation and the Copenhagen interpretation. Together with tunnelling and the energy quantisation theorem for conning potentials, formulated in the framework of quantum HJ equation, it leads to the main features of the axioms of quantum mechanics from a unique geometrical principle. Similar to the case of the classical HJ equation, this xes its quantum analog by requiring that there exist point transformations, rather than canonical ones, leading to the trivial hamiltonian. This is equivalent to a basic cocycle condition on the states. Such a cocycle condition can be implemented on compact spaces, so that continuous energy spectra are allowed only as a limiting case. Remarkably, a compact space would also imply that the Dirac and von Neumann formulations of quantum mechanics essentially coincide. We suggest that there is a denition of time parameterisation leading to trajectories in the context of the quantum HJ equation having the probabilistic interpretation of the Copenhagen School.
1 Introduction
The validity of quantum mechanics is indisputable, but it leaves many conceptual problems unresolved. For this reason over the years numerous schemes have been proposed to
a e-mail: [email protected]
address such issues. Among those, the quantum Hamilton Jacobi (HJ) theory is one of the most investigated topics; see [18] for a partial list of papers. These studies involve the foundation of quantum mechanics, in particular its interpretation, cosmology, the analysis of quantum dynamics, molecular trajectories, etc. It has been suggested that the quantum HamiltonJacobi equation (QHJE) yields a trajectory representation of quantum mechanics (see e.g. [9,10] and references therein). The absence of trajectories is, however, inherent in the Copenhagen probabilistic interpretation of the quantum mechanical wave function. There appears, therefore, to be a fundamental dichotomy between the two approaches. In this paper we offer a solution to this puzzle. We demonstrate the absence of trajectories in the derivation of the QHJE from point transformations leading to the trivial hamiltonian [1118]. The basic point is that trajectories can only be dened by time parameterisation of them, and include the Bohmde Broglie pilot wave representation and Floyds time parameterisation [1927] by using Jacobi theorem. We show in this paper that these time parameterisations are ill dened. This resolves the dichotomy with the Copenhangen interpretation.
In [28], we considered a Legendre duality in the framework of the Schrdinger equation. Consistency of this mathematical structure in the context of the phase space reveals that classical mechanics must be modied [1117]. The main idea has been to implement, as in the derivation of the classical HJ equation, the transformations leading to the free state. The difference is that we did not consider the usual canonical transformation with the space coordinate q and the conjugate momentum p considered as independent variables. Rather, we performed the transformation on q and considered the transformation on p as the one induced by the coordinate transformation, by assuming that the analog of the Hamilton characteristic function transforms as a scalar eld. Such a transformation leads to a basic cocycle condition which, in turn, implies that the analog of the Hamilton characteristic function must satisfy the quantum analog of the stationary HJ
123
2694 Page 2 of 7 Eur. Phys. J. C (2014) 74:2694
equation. The derivation extends to the higher dimensional non-stationary case and to the relativistic case as well [18].
A basic theorem in [1117] is that energy quantisation for bound states follows as a consistency condition. We stress that, whereas in the standard approach energy quantisation is a direct consequence of the wave-function interpretation, here it follows from the cocycle condition without any assumption on the meaning of the wave function.
The quantum HamiltonJacobi equation is
S
t +
1
2m (S)2 + V h2
2m
R
R = 0, (1)
R2
t +
1m ( R2S) = 0, (2)
which can be obtained by identifying a solution of the Schrdinger equation with Re
ih S . Note that S is the quantum
analog of Hamiltons principal function. Let us now consider a particle in a stationary state with energy E. We have
S = p dq E(t t0), (3)
where the rst term, which we denote by S0, is the quan
tum analog of Hamiltons characteristic function. Let us now assume that such a particle admits a trajectory q = q(t).
Performing a variation of time and energy, keeping xed the initial and nal spatial coordinates of the trajectory, we have
S =
S0
E E (t t0)E Et, and by Eq. (3)
t t0 =
S0
E . (4) This is the time parameterisation of particle trajectories that, as rst observed by Floyd [1927], should be used in considering the quantum HJ equation. This is just how trajectories are dened in CM as it implies the group velocity.
A simple but basic initial observation is that in the case of quantised spectra it is not possible to make the variation of the energy. In particular, the trajectories q = q(t), which would
follow by inverting Eq. (4), do not exist in the case of discrete energy spectra. Consistency arguments also show that this excludes the possibility of using Eq. (4) even in the case of continuous energy spectra. It is clear that the non-existence of trajectories suggests that also the probabilistic interpretation may be derived without imposing it as a basic axiom.
As we will see, there is a connection between the nonexistence of trajectories and the cocycle condition. In particular, we will see that the implementation of the cocycle condition xes gluing conditions on the ratio of two linearly independent solutions of the wave function that can be satised only on compact spaces, so that continuous energy spectra arise only in the decompactication limit. The fact
that such gluing conditions are a basic step in the geometrical formulation of [1118], related to Legendre duality [28], and the fact that they led to the quantisation of the energy in the case of conning potentials, suggest that they should be always satised. It should be observed that in the case of a free particle the level spacing of the energy spectrum will be determined by the geometry of our three-dimensional space, essentially of the order R2, where R is some characteristic cosmological length, and therefore extremely tiny. This, of course, does not mean that such a spacing could not be detected a priori. The fact that trajectories cannot be well dened provides an intriguing relation between quantum HJ theory and the Copenhagen interpretation. However, the reason why they do not exist in the quantum HJ theory is that it is just the time parameterisation that does not exist. In some sense a similar view is also the one of the Copenhagen interpretation. Actually, time is not a (self-adjoint) operator, so that also in standard quantum mechanics time is not an observable.
There are additional reasons to consider the possibility that a free particle may have a quantised energy spectrum, even if the level spacing is extremely tiny. A rigourous treatment of continuous spectra requires elaborated structures and the probability of nding the particle in a given volume cannot be dened. Furthermore, it should be observed that there are two formulations of quantum mechanics in the framework of the Copenhagen interpretation. We have the one by von Neumann [29], where quantum states are always rays in the Hilbert space L2(R), and the one by Dirac [30], which in general requires a rigged Hilbert space and eigenfunctionals. In particular, in the Dirac formulation, the wave function of a free particle in R3 is seen as a tempered distribution, that is, an element in S (
Rn), the dual space of the Schwarz space
S(Rn). In the case of compact spaces the Helmholtz equation
h2
2m = Ehas only a discrete spectrum, so that the two formulations would essentially coincide. More generally, a compact space would x some natural cutoff that may play an important rle. We also consider the problem of dening a sort of probabilistic time such that the resulting trajectories in the quantum HJ theory reproduce the probabilistic interpretation of the Copenhagen School.
2 The cocycle condition and energy quantisation
We dene
W(q) = V (q) E,where V is the potential energy and E the energy level. The main point of [1117] is to assume the existence transforma-
123
Eur. Phys. J. C (2014) 74:2694 Page 3 of 7 2694
tions leading any system to the one with trivial hamiltonian, that is, with W(q) = 0. Doing this in CM leads to the clas
sical HJ equation. The difference in the approach of [1117] is that, whereas in CM one considers the canonical transformations, where p and q are considered independent, we considered point transformations. More precisely, we considered the transformation of q and xed the transformation on the conjugate momentum as the one induced by the relation p = qS0, by considering S0, the analog of the Hamil
ton characteristic function, as a scalar function under such a transformation of q. The derivation can be extended to the non-stationary case and to the relativistic version as well [18].Therefore, the derivation of [11,18] is based on the principle that all physical states labelled by the function W(q) can be
connected by a coordinate transformation,
qa qb = qb(qa), dened by
Sb0(qb) = Sa0(qa).
This implies that there always exists a coordinate transformation connecting any physical state to the one with W0(q0) =
0. Inversely, this means that any physical state can be reached from the one with W0(q0) = 0 by a coordinate transforma
tion. This cannot be consistent with CM. The reason is that in CM the physical system with W0(q0) = 0 remains a xed
point under coordinate transformations. Thus, in CM it is not possible to generate all systems by a coordinate transformation from the trivial one. This implies a modication of CM, which is analysed by adding a still unknown function Q(q) to the classical HJ equation. Consistency conditions then x the transformation properties for W(q),
Wv(qv) =
qv qa
higher dimensions [18], implies that S0 is a solution of the
quantum stationary HJ equation (QSHJE),
1
2m
qS0 2 +V (q) E + h24m {S0, q} = 0. (6)
The equivalence with the one-dimensional stationary version of Eqs. (1) and (2) follows by observing that by Eq. (2) one gets
R = c
1
S 0,
with c a non-zero constant, so that
R
R =
1
2{S0, q}.
It is easy to check that the solution of Eq. (6) can be expressed in terms of solutions of the Schrdinger equation. In particular,
e
2i
h S0 = ei
w i
,
w + i
where = 1 + i 2, with 1 and 2 = 0 two arbitrary
constants, and w = D/, with D and two real linearly
independent solutions of the Schrdinger equation,
h2
2m
2Wa(qa) + (qa; qv)
and
Qv(qv) =
qv qa
2q2 + V (q) E (q) = 0.
A distinguished feature of the formalism in [1117] is that both solutions of the Schrdinger equation, and D, are kept in the formalism. This can be seen from the properties of the Schwarzian derivative that show that the trivialising transformation is
q q0 = ( D/),where ( D/) is an arbitrary Mbius transformation of D/. In general, the wave function in the formulation of [1117] is
(q) = R(q)
Ae
2 Qa(qa) (qa; qv), which xes the cocycle condition
(qa; qc) =
qc qb
2 (qa; qb) (qc; qb) . (5)
The cocycle condition is invariant under Mbius transformations and xes the functional form of the inhomogeneous term. Furthermore, the cocycle condition xes the identication
W(q) = h24m {e(2iS0/h), q}
and
Q(q) = h2
4m {S0, q},
where { f, q} = f /f 32( f /f )2 denotes the Schwarzian
derivative. The cocycle condition, which generalises to
ih S0 + Be
ih S0
. (7)
Furthermore, consistency conditions imply that S0(q) is
never a constant. In particular, the quantum potential Q(q) is never trivial and plays the rle of intrinsic energy.
The formulation in [1117] extends to higher dimensions and to the relativistic case as well [18]. Let us now review how energy quantisation arises in our formalism. The QSHJE is equivalent to the equation
{w, q} = 4m(V (q) E)/h2.
This implies that w = const, w C2(R) and w is differen
tiable on R. In addition, from the properties of the Schwarzian derivative it follows that
123
2694 Page 4 of 7 Eur. Phys. J. C (2014) 74:2694
{w, q1} = q4{w, q},which can be seen as a direct consequence of the cocycle condition. However, such a relation is dened only if the conditions on w hold on the extended real line R =
R
with S a solution of the quantum HJ equation. In classical
HJ theory time parameterisation is given by
t t0 =
Scl0
{}.
E , (11) which leads to the group velocity. In CM this is equivalent to identifying the conjugate and mechanical momenta. Namely, setting
p =
Scl0
q = m qyields Eq. (11). Bohmian mechanics therefore brings back the notion of trajectories for point particles, since we may solve for q(t). However, we note that the agreement between the denition of time parameterisation of trajectories by Eq. (10) and its denition by the Jacobi theorem (11) is no longer true in quantum mechanics. The use of the latter denition in quantum mechanics, that is,
t t0 =
S0
That is, w = const, w C2( R) with w differentiable on
R
and
w() = +
w(+) if w() = , w(+) if w() = .
(8)
This means that w, and therefore the trivialising map, is a local homeomorphism of R into itself. This implies the
continuity of ( D, ) and ( D , ) without assuming the probability interpretation of the wave function. In particular, the QSHJE is dened only if the ratio w = D/ of a
pair of real linearly independent solutions of the Schrdinger equation is a local homeomorphism of the extended real line
R=
R
{} into itself. This is an important feature, as
the L2(R) condition, which in the Copenhagen formulation is a consequence of the axiomatic interpretation of the wave function, directly follows as a basic theorem which only uses the geometrical gluing conditions of w at q = . In par
ticular, denoting by q (q+) the lowest (highest) q for which
V (q) E changes sign, we have [1117] the following.
If
V (q) E
P2 > 0, q < q,
P2+ > 0, q > q+ ,
E , (12) has been rst proposed by Floyd [1927]. In quantum HJ theory this leads to
m dq
dt =
qS01 E(V + Q)
.
(9)
then w = D/ is a local self-homeomorphism of R iff the
Schrdinger equation has an L2(R) solution.
Thus, since the QSHJE is dened if and only if w is a local self-homeomorphism of R, this theorem implies that energy
quantisation directly follows from the QSHJE itself without further assumptions.
3 Time parameterisation
We emphasise that the present approach is fundamentally distinct from the Bohmian one [1117]. Bohmian mechanics sets
(q) = R(q)ei S/h,where is the wave function. On the other hand, implementation of the point transformations leading to the trivial hamiltonian necessitates that the wave function is taken in the general form of Eq. (7). Such a condition is reminiscent of the necessity in quantum eld theories of using the two solutions of the relativistic quantum equations.
In Bohmian mechanics, time parameterisation is dened by identifying p with the mechanical momentum,
p =
S
q = m q, (10)
Therefore, in quantum mechanics the time parameterisation in Eq. (10) does not coincide with its denition via the Jacobi theorem.
The Floyd proposal (12) would in principle provide a trajectory representation of quantum mechanics which would seem to be in contradiction with the inherently probabilistic nature of quantum mechanics. We show that the denition (12) cannot be implemented. We emphasise, however, that this does not mean that the parameterisation provided by Eq. (12) cannot be useful. In fact, it is quite effective to perform semi-classical approximations. In this respect we note the successful application in studies of molecular dynamics [9,10].
It is clear that in the case of quantised energy spectra Eq. (12) is not dened. On the other hand, the concept of a trajectory should be a universal one, so that one should consider a time parameterisation which is consistent in both cases, discrete and continuous spectra. This essentially would exclude Eq. (12) also in the case of continuous spectra. There is, however, a more stringent argument to show that Eq. (12) cannot be used to dene time parameterisation of trajectories. In particular, we now show that the QSHJE is dened only in the case of a discrete spectrum with the case of continuous spectrum arising only as a limiting case. We saw that the cocycle condition led to the QSHJE written as a Schwarzian equation. In particular, we established that the gluing conditions should always hold. Let us now consider the case of a continuous spectrum. Without loss of generality, we may consider
123
Eur. Phys. J. C (2014) 74:2694 Page 5 of 7 2694
the case when for large q the potential is zero. For large q two associated real independent solutions of the Schdinger equation are
= sin kq , D = cos kq.
This means that for large q we have
w = tan kq.
On the other hand, whereas this function at nite distance is a local homeomorphism, it is not the case when considering the entire real axis. This can also be seen by considering a free particle in an innitely deep well and considering the periodicity conditions. This is equivalent to considering the particle in S1 and then sending its radius R to innity. For any nite R the ratio of two linearly independent solutions is a local homeomorphism of S1 and the spectrum is discrete.In the R limit the gluing condition is no longer under
control. In the case of the free particle in an innitely deep potential well of width L, the energy levels are
En = h2
2 2mL2 n2,
n
N+. It follows that for any nite value of L the spectrum
is discrete. We then conclude that imposing the cocycle condition requires a discrete spectrum, which in turn implies that continuous variation of the energy is not possible. Equivalently, the time parameterisation by the Jacobi theorem is not well dened. This can be generalised to the free particle in any space dimension, leading to the same conclusion. On the other hand, it is a general theorem that the equation
h2
Hilbert space, the role of time is apparent, through interference, just when the physical system is the superposition of at least two energy levels. Equation (13) indicates that the interference phenomena are deeply related to the concept of time.
Whereas Eq. (13) sheds light on the origin of interference in the quantum HamiltonJacobi formulation, there is an interesting alternative which is suggested by the Schrdinger equation. One may think that time parameterisation may be dened as a sort of random parameter whose distribution is xed by the properties of the distribution of the energy eigenvalues. In other words, instead of considering a nite difference, which gives t = t(E), we may search for a more intrin
sic denition. The idea is that the wave function depends on E, so one may formally invert this relation to E = E().
This leads us to consider t = t(). In particular, consider
a time-independent potential. In this case the Schrdinger equation implies
(q, t) =
k
cke
i h
Ekt k(q), (14)
where the k are the hamiltonian eigenfunctions
Hk = Enk.
Next, recall that for one-dimensional bound states n can be normalised in such a way that it takes real values. Multiplying Eq. (14) by n and integrating over R one gets
t =
i h
En
ln
R
ndq ln
R
(q, 0)ndq
2m = E,in bounded domains of Rn, therefore including e.g. the (n 1)-sphere Sn1, has only a discrete spectrum. At the
level of the quantum HJ equation, this is just a consequence of the non-triviality of the quantum potential.
Therefore, without using any axiomatic interpretation of the wave function, we have shown that trajectories cannot be derived from the quantum HJ equation. In particular, the concept of a localised particle with a well-dened velocity does not exist. Since trajectories do not exist in the formulation of [1117], one may try to consider nite differences instead of derivatives,
tn = S0
(En+1) S0(En)En+1 En
. (15)
Note, however, that t is just the time experienced by the observer. This suggests that there exists a kind of time parameterisation leading to the probabilistic interpretation of trajectories in the framework of the quantum HJ equation.
4 Conclusions
Understanding the synthesis of quantum mechanics and general relativity remains the pivotal goal of fundamental physics. The main effort in this endeavour is in the framework of string theory. String theory provides a self-consistent perturbative approach to quantum gravity. The main achievement of string theory is that it gives rise to the gauge and matter ingredients of elementary particle physics, and it predicts the number of degrees of freedom required to obtain a consistent theory. String theory therefore enables the development of a phenomenological approach to quantum gravity. The state of the art in this regard is the construction of Minimal Standard Heterotic String Models [3135]. Over the past few years important progress has also been achieved in the understanding of the perturbative expansion of string
. (13)
This is a basic point since it leads one to consider the superposition of different energy eigenstates, which is at the basis of the interference phenomena. In particular, whereas time evolution of a hamiltonian eigenfunction corresponds to an overall phase, so that it describes the same ray vector in the
123
2694 Page 6 of 7 Eur. Phys. J. C (2014) 74:2694
theory for genus g Riemann surfaces; see for example [36 45] and references therein. Despite its success, string theory does not provide a conceptual starting point for formulating quantum gravity. What we seek is a fundamental hypothesis of which, possibly, string theories arise as perturbative limits. A basic property of string theory is T-duality [46], which may be viewed as phase-space duality in compact space.
In this paper we examined the denability of time parameterisation of trajectories in the framework of the quantum HJ equation. We rst observed that it is not possible to perform innitesimal variations of the energy when this is quantised. As such, the quantum HJ equation does not lead to the concept of trajectory. Next, we discussed the identication of the mechanical momentum with the conjugate momentum,
m q =
S
q ,
as done in Bohmian mechanics, and we noticed that it is inconsistent with its derivation from Jacobis theorem, which in turn cannot be applied in the case of systems with quantised energy. On the other hand, consistency arguments show that if trajectories cannot be dened in the case of quantised energy, then trajectories do not exist even when the energy spectrum is continuous.
In this respect it should, however, be stressed that quantum trajectories provide a powerful approximation tool in quantum dynamics [9,10,47]. In particular, the method of quantum trajectories has been developed as a computational tool to solve time-dependent quantum mechanical problems by evolving ensembles of correlated quantum trajectories through the integration of the hydrodynamic equations. These quantum trajectories serve as a computational adaptive moving grid, and from this perspective these are not authentic trajectories.
We then proposed that the above features of the quantum HJ equation are at the heart of the probabilistic nature of quantum mechanics. In this respect, we considered time as dependent on the wave function, getting an expression that suggests considering time itself as having a probabilistic nature.
We also observed that the derivation of the quantum HJ equation from the cocycle condition [1117] is naturally formulated in compact spaces that can be extended considering the decompactication limit. This suggests that our space is compact. In this case all the possible energy spectra are quantised and would make the Dirac and von Neumann formulations of quantum mechanics essentially equivalent. The compactness of space has basic observational consequences and forthcoming evidence for it may exist in the cosmic microwave background radiation [48].
Acknowledgments AEF is supported by STFC under contract ST/J0 00493/1. MM is supported by the Padova University Project CPDA1193 49 and by the MIUR-PRIN contract 2009-KHZKRX.
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License which permits any use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author(s) and the source are credited.
Article funded by SCOAP3 and licensed under CC BY 4.0
References
1. V. Periwal, Phys. Rev. Lett. 80, 4366 (1998)2. M.H. Partovi, Phys. Rev. Lett. 89, 144101 (2002)3. D. Drr, S. Goldstein, R. Tumulka, N. Zangh, Phys. Rev. Lett. 93, 090402 (2004)
4. C. Meier, Phys. Rev. Lett. 93, 173003 (2004)5. M. Roncadelli, L.S. Schulman, Phys. Rev. Lett. 99, 170406 (2007)6. C.-C. Chou, A.S. Sanz, S. Miret-Arts, R.E. Wyatt, Phys. Rev. Lett. 102, 250401 (2009)
7. W. Koch, F. Grossmann, D.J. Tannor, Phys. Rev. Lett. 105, 230405 (2010)
8. B. Vakili, N. Khosravi, Phys. Rev. D 85, 083529 (2012)9. R.E. Wyatt, Quantum dynamics with trajectories: introduction to quantum hydrodynamics (Springer, Berlin, 2005)
10. B. Poirier, J. Chem. Phys. 121, 4501 (2004)11. A.E. Faraggi, M. Matone, Phys. Lett. B 450, 34 (1999)12. A.E. Faraggi, M. Matone, Phys. Lett. B 437, 369 (1998)13. A.E. Faraggi, M. Matone, Phys. Lett. A 249, 180 (1998)14. A.E. Faraggi, M. Matone, Phys. Lett. B 445, 77 (1998)15. A.E. Faraggi, M. Matone, Phys. Lett. B 445, 357 (1998)16. A.E. Faraggi, M. Matone, Int. J. Mod. Phys. A 15, 1869 (2000)17. A.E. Faraggi, M. Matone, Contribute to the book Quantum Trajectories, ed. P. Chattaraj, Taylor & Francis, Oxford (2011). (http://arxiv.org/abs/arXiv:0912.1225
Web End =arXiv: http://arxiv.org/abs/arXiv:0912.1225
Web End =0912.1225 )
18. G. Bertoldi, A.E. Faraggi, M. Matone, Class. Quantum Gravity 17, 3965 (2000)
19. E.R. Floyd, Phys. Rev. D 25, 1547 (1982)20. E.R. Floyd, Phys. Rev. D 26, 1339 (1982)21. E.R. Floyd, Phys. Rev. D 29, 1842 (1984)22. E.R. Floyd, Phys. Rev. D 34, 3246 (1986)23. E.R. Floyd, Found. Phys. Lett. 9, 489 (1996)24. E.R. Floyd, Found. Phys. Lett. 13, 235 (2000)25. E.R. Floyd, Phys. Lett. A 214, 259 (1996)26. E.R. Floyd, Int. J. Mod. Phys. A 14, 1111 (1999)27. E.R. Floyd, Int. J. Mod. Phys 15, 1363 (2000)28. A.E. Faraggi, M. Matone, Phys. Rev. Lett. 78, 163 (1997)29. J. von Neumann, Mathematical foundations of quantum mechanics. Princeton University Press, Princeton (1996)
30. P.A.M. Dirac, The Principles of Quantum Mechanics. Oxford University Press, Oxford (1988)
31. A.E. Faraggi, D.V. Nanopoulos, K. Yuan, Nucl. Phys. B 335, 347 (1990)
32. A.E. Faraggi, Phys. Lett. B 278, 131 (1992)33. A.E. Faraggi, Nucl. Phys. B 387, 239 (1992)34. G.B. Cleaver, A.E. Faraggi, D.V. Nanopoulos, Phys. Lett. B 455, 135 (1999)
35. K. Christodoulides, A.E. Faraggi, J. Rizos, Phys. Lett. B 702, 81 (2011)
36. M. Matone, R. Volpato, Nucl. Phys. B 732, 321 (2006)37. M. Matone, R. Volpato, Nucl. Phys. B 806, 735 (2009)38. M. Matone, R. Volpato, Nucl. Phys. B 839, 21 (2010)39. M. Matone, R. Volpato, Proc. Am. Math. Soc. 141, 2575 (2013)40. M. Matone, R. Volpato, Math. Ann. 355, 327 (2013)
123
Eur. Phys. J. C (2014) 74:2694 Page 7 of 7 2694
41. M. Matone, R. Volpato, J. Math. Phys. 52, 102305 (2011)42. M. Matone, Int. J. Mod. Phys. A 10, 289 (1995)43. M. Matone, JHEP 1210, 175 (2012)44. M. Matone, JHEP 1211, 050 (2012)
45. M. Matone, Phys. Rev. D 89, 026008 (2014)46. A. Giveon, M. Porrati, E. Rabinovici, Phys. Rep. 244, 77 (1994)47. R.E. Wyatt, J. Chem. Phys. 117, 9569 (2002)48. G. Aslanyan, A.V. Manohar, JCAP 1206, 003 (2012)
123
You have requested "on-the-fly" machine translation of selected content from our databases. This functionality is provided solely for your convenience and is in no way intended to replace human translation. Show full disclaimer
Neither ProQuest nor its licensors make any representations or warranties with respect to the translations. The translations are automatically generated "AS IS" and "AS AVAILABLE" and are not retained in our systems. PROQUEST AND ITS LICENSORS SPECIFICALLY DISCLAIM ANY AND ALL EXPRESS OR IMPLIED WARRANTIES, INCLUDING WITHOUT LIMITATION, ANY WARRANTIES FOR AVAILABILITY, ACCURACY, TIMELINESS, COMPLETENESS, NON-INFRINGMENT, MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR A PARTICULAR PURPOSE. Your use of the translations is subject to all use restrictions contained in your Electronic Products License Agreement and by using the translation functionality you agree to forgo any and all claims against ProQuest or its licensors for your use of the translation functionality and any output derived there from. Hide full disclaimer
The Author(s) 2014
Abstract
(ProQuest: ... denotes formulae and/or non-USASCII text omitted; see image)
We show that if space is compact, then trajectories cannot be defined in the framework of the quantum Hamilton-Jacobi (HJ) equation. The starting point is the simple observation that when the energy is quantised it is not possible to make variations with respect to the energy, and the time parameterisation ......, implied by Jacobi's theorem, which leads to the group velocity, is ill defined. It should be stressed that this follows directly from the quantum HJ equation without any axiomatic assumption concerning the standard formulation of quantum mechanics. This provides a stringent connection between the quantum HJ equation and the Copenhagen interpretation. Together with tunnelling and the energy quantisation theorem for confining potentials, formulated in the framework of quantum HJ equation, it leads to the main features of the axioms of quantum mechanics from a unique geometrical principle. Similar to the case of the classical HJ equation, this fixes its quantum analog by requiring that there exist point transformations, rather than canonical ones, leading to the trivial hamiltonian. This is equivalent to a basic cocycle condition on the states. Such a cocycle condition can be implemented on compact spaces, so that continuous energy spectra are allowed only as a limiting case. Remarkably, a compact space would also imply that the Dirac and von Neumann formulations of quantum mechanics essentially coincide. We suggest that there is a definition of time parameterisation leading to trajectories in the context of the quantum HJ equation having the probabilistic interpretation of the Copenhagen School.
You have requested "on-the-fly" machine translation of selected content from our databases. This functionality is provided solely for your convenience and is in no way intended to replace human translation. Show full disclaimer
Neither ProQuest nor its licensors make any representations or warranties with respect to the translations. The translations are automatically generated "AS IS" and "AS AVAILABLE" and are not retained in our systems. PROQUEST AND ITS LICENSORS SPECIFICALLY DISCLAIM ANY AND ALL EXPRESS OR IMPLIED WARRANTIES, INCLUDING WITHOUT LIMITATION, ANY WARRANTIES FOR AVAILABILITY, ACCURACY, TIMELINESS, COMPLETENESS, NON-INFRINGMENT, MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR A PARTICULAR PURPOSE. Your use of the translations is subject to all use restrictions contained in your Electronic Products License Agreement and by using the translation functionality you agree to forgo any and all claims against ProQuest or its licensors for your use of the translation functionality and any output derived there from. Hide full disclaimer